Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
\chapter{Unique factorization and the class group} | |
Commutative rings in general do not admit unique factorization. | |
Nonetheless, for many rings (``integrally closed'' rings), which | |
includes the affine coordinate rings one obtains in algebraic geometry when | |
one studies smooth varieties, there is an invariant called the ``class | |
group'' that measures the failure of unique factorization. This ``class | |
group'' is a certain quotient of codimension one primes (geometrically, | |
codimension one subvarieties) modulo rational equivalence. | |
Many even nicer rings have the convenient property that their localizations at prime | |
ideals \emph{factorial}, a key example being the coordinate ring of an affine | |
nonsingular variety. | |
For these even nicer rings, an alternative method of defining the class group | |
can be given: the class group corresponds to the group of isomorphism | |
classes of \emph{invertible modules}. Geometrically, such invertible modules | |
are line bundles on the associated variety (or scheme). | |
\section{Unique factorization} | |
\subsection{Definition} | |
We begin with the nicest of all possible cases, when the ring itself admits | |
unique factorization. | |
Let $R$ be a domain. | |
\begin{definition} | |
A nonzero element $x \in R$ is \textbf{prime} if $(x)$ is a prime ideal. | |
\end{definition} | |
In other words, $x$ is not a unit, and if $x \mid ab$, then either $x \mid a$ | |
or $x \mid b$. | |
We restate the earlier \cref{earlyUFD} slightly. | |
\begin{definition} | |
A domain $R$ is \textbf{factorial} (or a \textbf{unique factorization domain}, | |
or a \textbf{UFD}) if every nonzero noninvertible element $x \in R$ factors as a | |
product $ x_1 \dots x_n$ where each $x_i$ is prime. | |
\end{definition} | |
Recall that a \emph{principal ideal domain} is a UFD (\cref{PIDUFD}), as is a | |
\emph{euclidean} domain (\cref{EDPID}); actually, a euclidean domain is a PID. | |
Previously, we imposed something seemingly slightly stronger: that the | |
factorization be unique. We next show that we get that for free. | |
\begin{proposition}[The fundamental theorem of arithmetic] | |
This factorization is essentially unique, that is, up to multiplication by units. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} Let $x \in R$ be a nonunit. | |
Say $x = x_1 \dots x_n = y_1 \dots y_m$ were two different prime | |
factorizations. Then $m,n>0$. | |
We have that $x_1 \mid y_1 \dots y_m$, so $x_1 \mid y_i$ for some $i$. But | |
$y_i$ is prime. So $x_1$ and $y_i$ differ by a unit. By removing each of these, | |
we can get a smaller set of nonunique factorizations. | |
Namely, we find that | |
\[ x_2 \dots x_n = y_1 \dots \hat{y_i} \dots y_m \] | |
and then we can induct on the number of factors. | |
\end{proof} | |
The motivating example is of course: | |
\begin{example} | |
$\mathbb{Z}$ is factorial. This is the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, and | |
follows because $\mathbb{Z}$ is a euclidean domain. The same observation | |
applies to a polynomial ring over a field by \cref{polyringED}. | |
\end{example} | |
\subsection{Gauss's lemma} | |
We now show that factorial rings are closed under the operation of forming | |
polynomial rings. | |
\begin{theorem}[Gauss's lemma] | |
If $R$ is factorial, so is the polynomial ring $R[X]$. | |
\end{theorem} | |
In general, if $R$ is a PID, $R[X]$ will \emph{not} be a PID. For instance, | |
$\mathbb{Z}[X]$ is not a PID: the prime ideal $(2, X)$ is not principal. | |
\begin{proof} | |
In the course of this proof, we shall identify the prime elements in $R[X]$. | |
We start with a lemma that allows us to compare factorizations in $K[X]$ (for | |
$K$ the quotient field) and $R[X]$; the advantage is that we already know the | |
polynomial ring over a \emph{field} to be a UFD. | |
\begin{lemma} Suppose $R$ is a unique factorization domain with | |
quotient field $K$. | |
Suppose $f \in R[X]$ is irreducible in $R[X]$ and there is no nontrivial common divisor of | |
the coefficients of $f$. Then $f$ is irreducible in $K[X]$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
With this in mind, we say that a polynomial in $R[X]$ is \textbf{primitive} if | |
the coefficients have no common divisor in $R$. | |
\begin{proof} Indeed, suppose we had a factorization | |
\[ f = gh, \quad g, h \in K[X], \] | |
where $g,h$ have degree $\geq 1$. | |
Then we can clear denominators to find a factorization | |
\[ rf = g' h' \] | |
where $r \in R - \left\{0\right\}$ and $g', h' \in R[X]$. By clearing | |
denominators as little as possible, we may assume that $g',h'$ are primitive. | |
To be precise, we divide $g', h'$ by their \emph{contents.} Let us define: | |
\begin{definition} | |
The \textbf{content} $\cont (f)$ of a polynomial $f \in R[X]$ is the greatest common | |
divisor of its coefficients. The content of an element $f$ in $K[X]$ is defined | |
by considering $r \in R$ such that $rf \in R[X]$, and taking $\cont(rf)/r$. | |
This is well-defined, modulo elements of $R^*$, and we have $\cont(sf) = s \cont f$ if $s \in K$. | |
\end{definition} | |
To say that the content lies in $R$ is to say that the polynomial is in $R[X]$; | |
to say that the content is a unit is to say that the polynomial is primitive. | |
Note that a monic polynomial in $R[X]$ is primitive. | |
So we have: | |
\begin{lemma} | |
Any element of $K[X]$ is a product of $\cont(f)$ and something primitive in | |
$R[X]$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Indeed, $f/\cont(f)$ has content a unit. It therefore cannot have anything in the | |
denominator. Indeed, if it had a term $r/p^i X^n$ where $r ,p \in R$ and $p | |
\nmid r$ is prime, then the content would divide $r/p^i$. It thus could not be | |
in $R$. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
$\cont(fg) = \cont(f) \cont(g)$ if $f,g \in K[X]$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
By dividing $f,g$ by their contents, it suffices to show that the product of | |
two primitive polynomials in $R[X]$ (i.e. those with no common divisor of all | |
their coefficients) is itself primitive. Indeed, suppose $f,g$ are primitive | |
and $p \in R$ is a prime. Then $\overline{f}, \overline{g} \in R/(p)[X]$ are | |
nonzero. Their product $\overline{f}\overline{g}$ is also not zero because | |
$R/(p)[X]$ is a domain, $p$ being prime. In particular, $p$ is not a common | |
factor of the coefficients of $fg$. Since $p$ was arbitrary, this completes the | |
proof. | |
\end{proof} | |
So return to the main proof. We know that $f = gh$. We divided $g,h$ by their | |
contents to get $g', h' \in R[X]$. We had then | |
\[ r f = g' h', \quad r \in K^*. \] | |
Taking the contents, and using the fact that $f, g', h'$ are primitive, we have then: | |
\[ r = \cont(g') \cont(h') = 1 \quad \mathrm{(modulo \ } R^*). \] | |
But then $f = r^{-1} g' h'$ shows that $f$ is not irreducible in $R[X]$, | |
contradiction. | |
\end{proof} | |
Let $R$ be a ring. Recall that an element is \textbf{irreducible} if it admits | |
no nontrivial factorization. The product of an irreducible element and a unit | |
is irreducible. | |
Call a ring \textbf{finitely irreducible} if every element in the ring admits a | |
factorization into finitely many irreducible elements. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
A ring $R$ is finitely irreducible if every ascending sequence of | |
\emph{principal} ideals in $R$ stabilizes. | |
\end{lemma} | |
A ring such that every ascending sequence of ideals (not necessarily | |
principal) stabilizes is said to be \emph{noetherian;} this is a highly useful | |
finiteness condition on a ring. | |
\begin{proof} | |
Suppose $R$ satisfies the ascending chain condition on principal ideals. Then | |
let $x \in R$. We would like to show it can be factored as a product of | |
irreducibles. | |
So suppose $x$ is not the product of finitely many irreducibles. In particular, | |
it is reducible: $x = x_1 x_1'$, where neither factor is a unit. One of this | |
cannot be written as a finite product of irreducibles. Say it is $x_1$. | |
Similarly, we can write $x_1 = x_2 x_2''$ where one of the factors, wlog $x_2$, | |
is not the product of finitely many irreducibles. Repeating inductively gives | |
the ascending sequence | |
\[ (x) \subset (x_1) \subset (x_2) \subset \dots, \] | |
and since each factorization is nontrivial, the inclusions are each nontrivial. | |
This is a contradiction. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
Suppose $R$ is a UFD. Then every ascending sequence of principal ideals in | |
$R[X]$ stabilizes. In particular, $R[X]$ is finitely irreducible. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Suppose $(f_1) \subset (f_2) \subset \dots \in R[X]$. Then each $f_{i+1} \mid | |
f_{i}$. In particular, the degrees of $f_i$ are nonincreasing, and consequently | |
stabilize. Thus for $i \gg 0$, we have $\deg f_{i+1} = \deg f_i$. | |
We can thus assume that all the degrees are the same. In this case, if $i \gg | |
0$ and $k>0$, | |
$f_{i}/f_{i+k} \in R[X]$ must actually lie in $R$ as $R$ is a domain. | |
In particular, throwing out the first few elements in the sequence if | |
necessary, it follows that our sequence looks like | |
\[ f, f/r_1, f/(r_1r_2), \dots \] | |
where the $r_i \in R$. However, we can only continue this a finite amount of | |
time before the $r_i$'s will have to become units since $R$ is a UFD. (Or $f | |
= 0$.) | |
So the sequence of ideals stabilizes. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
Every element in $R[X]$ can be factored into a product of irreducibles. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} Now evident from the preceding lemmata. | |
\end{proof} | |
Suppose $P$ is an irreducible element in $R[X]$. I claim that $P$ is prime. | |
There are two cases: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $P \in R$ is a prime in $R$. Then we know that $P \mid f$ if and only if | |
the coefficients of $f$ are divisible by $P$. In particular, $P \mid f$ iff $P | |
\mid \cont (f)$. It is now clear that $P \mid fg$ if and only if $P$ divides | |
one of $\cont(f), \cont(g)$ (since $\cont(fg) = \cont(f) \cont(g)$). | |
\item $P$ does not belong to $R$. Then $P$ must have content a unit or it would | |
be divisible by its content. | |
So $P$ is irreducible in $K[X]$ by the above reasoning. | |
Say we have an expression | |
\[ P \mid fg, \quad f,g \in R[X]. \] | |
Since $P$ is irreducible, hence prime, in the UFD (even PID) $K[X]$, we have | |
that $P $ divides one of $f,g$ in $K[X]$. Say we can write | |
\[ f = q P , q \in K[X]. \] | |
Then taking the content shows that $\cont(q) = \cont(f) \in R$, so $q \in | |
R[X]$. It follows that $P \mid f$ in $R[X]$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
We have shown that every element in $R[X]$ factors into a product of prime | |
elements. From this, it is clear that $R[X]$ is a UFD. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{corollary} | |
The polynomial ring $k[X_1, \dots, X_n]$ for $k$ a field is factorial. | |
\end{corollary} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Induction on $n$. | |
\end{proof} | |
\subsection{Factoriality and height one primes} | |
We now want to give a fancier criterion for a ring to be a UFD, in terms of the | |
lattice | |
structure on $\spec R$. This will require a notion from dimension theory (to be | |
developed more fully later). | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $R$ be a domain. A prime ideal $\mathfrak{p} \subset R$ is said to be of | |
\textbf{height one} if $\mathfrak{p}$ is minimal among ideals | |
containing $x$ for some nonzero $x \in R$. | |
\end{definition} | |
So a prime of height one is not the zero prime, but it is as close to zero as | |
possible, in some sense. When we later talk about dimension theory, we will | |
talk about primes of any height. In a sense, $\mathfrak{p}$ is ``almost'' | |
generated by one element. | |
\begin{theorem} \label{heightonefactoriality} | |
Let $R$ be a noetherian domain. The following are equivalent: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $R$ is factorial. | |
\item Every height one prime is principal. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{theorem} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Let's first show 1) implies 2). Assume $R$ is factorial and $\mathfrak{p}$ is | |
height one, minimal containing $(x)$ for some $x \neq 0 \in R$. | |
Then $x$ is a nonunit, and it is nonzero, so it has a prime factorization | |
\[ x = x_1 \dots x_n, \quad \mathrm{each \ } x_i \ \mathrm{prime}. \] | |
Some $x_i \in \mathfrak{p}$ because $\mathfrak{p}$ is prime. In particular, | |
\[ \mathfrak{p} \supset (x_i) \supset (x). \] | |
But $(x_i)$ is prime itself, and it contains $(x)$. The minimality of | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ says that $\mathfrak{p} = (x_i)$. | |
Conversely, suppose every height one prime is principal. Let $x \in R$ be | |
nonzero and a nonunit. We want | |
to factor $x$ as a product of primes. | |
Consider the ideal $(x) \subsetneq R$. As a result, $(x)$ is contained in a | |
prime ideal. Since $R$ is noetherian, there is a minimal prime ideal | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ containing $(x)$. Then $\mathfrak{p}$, being a height one | |
prime, is principal---say $\mathfrak{p}=(x_1)$. It follows that $x_1 \mid x$ | |
and $x_1$ is prime. | |
Say | |
\[ x = x_1 x_1'. \] | |
If $x_1'$ is a nonunit, repeat this process to get $x_1' = x_2 x_2'$ with $x_2$ a prime element. | |
Keep going; inductively we have | |
\[ x_k = x_{k+1}x_{k+1}'. \] | |
If this process stops, with one of the $x_k'$ a unit, we get a prime | |
factorization of $x$. Suppose the process | |
continues forever. Then we would have | |
\[ (x) \subsetneq (x_1') \subsetneq (x_2') \subsetneq (x_3') \subsetneq \dots, \] | |
which is impossible by noetherianness. | |
\end{proof} | |
We have seen that unique factorization can be formulated in terms of prime | |
ideals. | |
\subsection{Factoriality and normality} | |
We next state a generalization of the ``rational root theorem'' as in high | |
school algebra. | |
\begin{proposition} \label{factorialimpliesnormal} | |
A factorial domain is integrally closed. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
\add{proof -- may be in the queue already} | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{Weil divisors} | |
\label{weildivsec} | |
\subsection{Definition} | |
We start by discussing Weil divisors. | |
\begin{definition} | |
A \textbf{Weil divisor} for $R$ is a formal linear combination $\sum n_{i} | |
[\mathfrak{p}_i]$ where the $\mathfrak{p}_i$ range over height one primes of | |
$R$. So the group of Weil divisors is the free abelian group on the height one | |
primes of $R$. We denote this group by $\weil(R)$. | |
\end{definition} | |
The geometric picture behind Weil divisors is that a Weil divisor is like a | |
hypersurface: a subvariety of codimension one. | |
\subsection{Valuations} | |
\subsection{Nagata's lemma} We finish with a fun application of the exact | |
sequence of Weil divisors to a purely algebraic statement about factoriality. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
Let $A$ be a normal noetherian domain. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{theorem} | |
Let $A$ be a noetherian domain, $x \in A-\left\{0\right\}$. Suppose $(x)$ is | |
prime and $A_x$ is factorial. Then $A$ is factorial. | |
\end{theorem} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We first show that $A$ is normal (hence regular in codimension one). | |
Indeed, $A_x$ is normal. So if $t \in K(A)$ is integral over $A$, it lies in | |
$A_x$. | |
So we need to check that if $a/x^n \in A_x$ is integral over $A$ and $x \nmid | |
x$, then $n=0$. | |
Suppose we had an equation | |
\[ (a/x^n)^N + b_1 (a/x^n)^{N-1} + \dots + b_N = 0. \] | |
Multiplying both sides by $x^{nN}$ gives that | |
\[ a^N \in xR, \] | |
so $x \mid a$ by primality. | |
Now we use the exact sequence | |
\[ (x) \to \mathrm{Cl}(A) \to \mathrm{Cl}(A_x) \to 0. \] | |
The end is zero, and the image of the first map is zero. So | |
$\mathrm{Cl}(A)=0$. Thus $A$ is a UFD. | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{Locally factorial domains} | |
\subsection{Definition} | |
\begin{definition} | |
A noetherian domain $R$ is said to be \textbf{locally factorial} if | |
$R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is factorial for each $\mathfrak{p}$ prime. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{example} | |
The coordinate ring $\mathbb{C}[x_1, \dots, x_n/I$ of an algebraic variety is | |
locally factorial if the variety is smooth. We may talk about this later. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{example}[Nonexample] | |
Let $R$ be $\mathbb{C}[A,B,C,D]/(AD - BC)$. The spectrum of $R$ has maximal | |
ideals consisting of 2-by-2 matrices of determinant zero. This variety is very | |
singular at the origin. It is not even locally factorial at the origin. | |
The failure of unique factorization comes from the fact that | |
\[ AD = BC \] | |
in this ring $R$. This is a prototypical example of a ring without unique | |
factorization. The reason has to do with the fact that the variety has a | |
singularity at the origin. | |
\end{example} | |
\subsection{The Picard group} | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $R$ be a commutative ring. An $R$-module $I$ is \textbf{invertible} if | |
there exists $J$ such that | |
\[ I \otimes_R J \simeq R. \] | |
Invertibility is with respect to the tensor product. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{remark} \label{linebundremark} | |
In topology, one is often interested in classifying \emph{vector bundles} on | |
spaces. In algebraic geometry, a module $M$ over a ring $R$ gives (as in | |
\cref{}) a sheaf of abelian groups over the topological space $\spec R$; this | |
is supposed to be an analogy with the theory of vector bundles. (It is not so | |
implausible since the Serre-Swan theorem (\cref{}) gives an equivalence of | |
categories between the vector bundles over a compact space $X$ and the | |
projective modules over the ring $C(X)$ of continuous functions.) | |
In this analogy, the invertible modules are the \emph{line bundles}. | |
The definition has a counterpart in the topological setting: for instance, a | |
vector bundle $\mathcal{E} \to X$ over a space $X$ is a line bundle (that is, | |
of rank one) if and only if there is a vector bundle $\mathcal{E}' \to X$ such | |
that $\mathcal{E} \otimes \mathcal{E}'$ is the trivial bundle $X \times | |
\mathbb{R}$. | |
\end{remark} | |
There are many equivalent characterizations. | |
\begin{proposition} | |
Let $R$ be a ring, $I$ an $R$-module. TFAE: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $I$ is invertible. | |
\item $I$ is finitely generated and $I_{\mathfrak{p}} \simeq R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ for all primes | |
$\mathfrak{p} \subset R$. | |
\item $I$ is finitely generated and there exist $a_1, \dots, a_n \in R$ which generate $(1)$ | |
in $R$ such that | |
\[ I[a_i^{-1}]\simeq R[a_i^{-1}]. \] | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
First, we show that if $I$ is invertible, then $I$ is finitely generated. | |
Suppose $I \otimes_R J \simeq R$. This means that $1 \in R$ corresponds to an | |
element | |
\[ \sum i_k \otimes j_k \in I \otimes_R J . \] | |
Thus, there exists a finitely generated submodule $I_0\subset I$ such that the map $I_0 \otimes J \to I | |
\otimes J$ is surjective. Tensor this with $I$, so we get a surjection | |
\[ I_0 \simeq I_0 \otimes J \otimes I \to I \otimes J \otimes I \simeq I \] | |
which leads to a surjection $I_0 \twoheadrightarrow I$. This implies that $I$ | |
is finitely generated | |
\textbf{Step 1: 1 implies 2.} | |
We now show 1 implies 2. Note that if $I$ is invertible, then $I \otimes_R R'$ | |
is an invertible $R'$ module for any $R$-algebra $R'$; to get an inverse of | |
$I \otimes_R R'$, | |
tensor the inverse of $I$ with $R'$. | |
In particular, $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is an invertible $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$-module | |
for each $\mathfrak{p}$. As a result, | |
\[ I_{\mathfrak{p}}/\mathfrak{p} I_{\mathfrak{p}} \] | |
is invertible over the \emph{field} $R_{\mathfrak{p}}/\mathfrak{p}R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. This means | |
that | |
$ I_{\mathfrak{p}}/\mathfrak{p} I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is a one-dimensional vector | |
space over the residue field. (The invertible modules over a vector space are | |
the one-dimensional spaces.) | |
Choose an element $x \in I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ which generates | |
$I_{\mathfrak{p}}/\mathfrak{p}I_{\mathfrak{p}}$. Since $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is | |
finitely generated, Nakayama's lemma shows that $x$ generates $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$. | |
We get a surjection $\alpha: R_{\mathfrak{p}} \twoheadrightarrow I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ | |
carrying $1 \to x$. We claim that this map is injective. | |
This will imply that $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is free of rank 1. So, let $J$ be an | |
inverse of $I$ among $R$-modules, so that $I \otimes_R J = R$; the same | |
argument as above provides a surjection | |
$ \beta: {R}_{\mathfrak{p}} \to J_{\mathfrak{p}}$. | |
Then $\beta' = \beta \otimes 1_{I_{\mathfrak{p}}}: I_{\mathfrak{p}} \to | |
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is also a surjection. | |
Composing, we get a surjective map | |
\[ R_{\mathfrak{p}} \stackrel{\alpha}{\twoheadrightarrow} I_{\mathfrak{p}} | |
\stackrel{\beta'}{\twoheadrightarrow} R_{\mathfrak{p}} \] | |
whose composite must be multiplication by a unit, since the ring is local. Thus | |
the composite is injective and $\alpha$ is injective. | |
It follows that $\alpha$ is an isomorphism, so that $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is free | |
of rank one. | |
\textbf{Step 2: 2 implies 3.} | |
Now we show 2 implies 3. Suppose $I$ is finitely generated with generators $\left\{x_1, \dots, x_n\right\} \subset I$ and $I_{\mathfrak{p}} \simeq | |
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ for all $\mathfrak{p}$. Then for each $\mathfrak{p} | |
$, we can choose an element $x$ of $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ generating | |
$I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ as $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$-module. | |
By multiplying by the denominator, we can assume that $x \in I$. | |
By assumption, we can then find $a_i,s_i \in R$ with | |
\[ s_i x_i = a_i x \in R \] | |
for some $s_i \notin \mathfrak{p}$ as $x$ generates $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$. This means that $x$ generates $I$ after inverting the $s_i$. It | |
follows that $I[1/a] = R[1/a]$ where $a = \prod s_i \notin \mathfrak{p}$. | |
In particular, we find that there is an open covering $\{\spec | |
R[1/a_{\mathfrak{p}}] \}$ of $\spec R$ (where $a_{\mathfrak{p}} \notin | |
\mathfrak{p}$) on which $I$ is isomorphic to $R$. | |
To say that these cover $\spec R$ is to say that the $a_{\mathfrak{p}}$ | |
generate $1$. | |
Finally, let's do the implication 3 implies 1. Assume that we have the | |
situation of $I[1/a_i] \simeq R[1/a_i]$. We want to show that $I$ is invertible. | |
We start by showing that $I$ is \textbf{finitely presented}. This means that | |
there is an exact sequence | |
\[ R^m \to R^n \to I \to 0, \] | |
i.e. $I$ is the cokernel of a map between free modules of finite rank. | |
To see this, first, we've assumed that $I$ is finitely generated. So there is a | |
surjection | |
\[ R^n \twoheadrightarrow I \] | |
with a kernel $K \rightarrowtail R^n$. We must show that $K$ is finitely | |
generated. Localization is an exact functor, so $K[1/a_i]$ is the kernel of | |
$R[1/a_i]^n \to I[1/a_i]$. However, we have an exact sequence | |
\[ K[1/a_i] \rightarrowtail R[1/a_i]^n \twoheadrightarrow R[1/a_i] \] | |
by the assumed isomorphism $I[1/a_i] \simeq R[1/a_i]$. But since a free module | |
is projective, this sequence splits and we find that $K[1/a_i]$ is finitely | |
generated. If it's finitely generated, it's generated by finitely many elements | |
in $K$. | |
As a result, we find that there is a map | |
\[ R^N \to K \] | |
such that the localization to $\spec R[1/a_i]$ is surjective. This implies by | |
the homework that $R^N \to K$ is surjective.\footnote{To check that a map is | |
surjective, just check at the localizations at any maximal ideal.} Thus $K$ is finitely generated. | |
In any case, we have shown that the module $I$ is finitely presented. | |
\textbf{Define} $J = \hom_R(I, R)$ as the candidate for its dual. This | |
construction is compatible with localization. | |
We can choose a finite presentation $R^m \to R^n \to I \to 0$, which leads to a | |
sequence | |
\[ 0 \to J \to \hom(R^n, R) \to \hom(R^m, R). \] | |
It follows that the formation of $J$ commutes with localization. | |
In particular, this argument shows that | |
\[ J[1/a] = \hom_{R[1/a]}(I[1/a], R[1/a]). \] | |
One can check this by using the description of $J$. By construction, there is a | |
canonical map $I \otimes J \to R$. | |
I claim that this map is invertible. | |
For the proof, we use the fact that one can check for an isomorphism locally. | |
It suffices to show that | |
\[ I[1/a] \otimes J[1/a] \to R[1/a] \] | |
is an isomorphism for some collection of $a$'s that generate the unit ideal. | |
However, we have $a_1, \dots, a_n$ that generate the unit ideal such that | |
$I[1/a_i]$ is free of rank 1, hence so is $J[1/a_i]$. It thus follows that | |
$I[1/a_i] \otimes J[1/a_i]$ is an isomorphism. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $R$ be a commutative ring. We define the \textbf{Picard group} $\pic(R)$ to | |
be the set of isomorphism classes of invertible $R$-modules. This is an abelian | |
group; the addition law is defined so that the sum of the classes represented | |
by $M, N$ is $M \otimes_R N$. | |
The identity element is given by $R$. | |
\end{definition} | |
The Picard group is thus analogous (cf. \cref{linebundleremark}) to the set of | |
isomorphism classes of line bundles on a topological space (which is also an | |
abelian group). While the latter can often be easily computed (for a nice space | |
$X$, the line bundles are classified by elements of $H^2(X, \mathbb{Z})$), the | |
interpretation in the algebraic setting is more difficult. | |
\subsection{Cartier divisors} | |
Assume furthermore that $R$ is a domain. We now introduce: | |
\begin{definition} | |
A \textbf{Cartier divisor} for $R$ is a submodule $M \subset K(R)$ such that | |
$M$ is invertible. | |
\end{definition} | |
In other words, a Cartier divisor is an invertible fractional ideal. | |
Alternatively, it is an invertible $R$-module $M$ with a nonzero map $M \to | |
K(R)$. \textbf{ Once this map is nonzero, it is automatically injective,} since | |
injectivity can be checked at the localizations, and any module-homomorphism from a domain into | |
its quotient field is either zero or injective (because it is multiplication by | |
some element). | |
We now make this into a group. | |
\begin{definition} | |
Given $(M, a: M \hookrightarrow K(R))$ and $(N, b: N \hookrightarrow K(R))$, we | |
define the sum to be | |
\[ (M \otimes N, a \otimes b: M \otimes N \hookrightarrow K(R)). \] | |
The map $a \otimes b$ is nonzero, so by what was said above, it is an injection. | |
Thus the Cartier divisors from an abelian group $\cart(R)$. | |
\end{definition} | |
By assumption, there is a homomorphism | |
\[ \cart(R) \to\pic(R) \] | |
mapping $(M, M \hookrightarrow K(R)) \to M$. | |
\begin{proposition} | |
The map $\cart(R) \to \pic(R)$ is surjective. In other words, any invertible | |
$R$-module can be embedded in $K(R)$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} Let $M$ be an invertible $R$-module. | |
Indeed, we know that $M_{(0)} = M \otimes_R K(R)$ is an invertible | |
$K(R)$-module, so a one-dimensional vector space over $K(R)$. In particular, | |
$M_{(0)} \simeq K(R)$. There is a nonzero homomorphic map | |
\[ M \to M_{(0) } \simeq K(R), \] | |
which is automatically injective by the discussion above. | |
\end{proof} | |
What is the kernel of $\cart(R) \to \pic(R)$? This is the set of Cartier divisors which are | |
isomorphic to $R$ itself. In other words, it is the set of $(R, R | |
\hookrightarrow K(R))$. This data is the same thing as the data of a nonzero | |
element of $K(R)$. | |
So the kernel of | |
\[ \cart(R) \to \pic(R) \] | |
has kernel isomorphic to $K(R)^*$. We have a short exact sequence | |
\[ K(R)^* \to \cart(R) \to \pic(R) \to 0. \] | |
\subsection{Weil divisors and Cartier divisors} | |
Now, we want to assume $\cart(R)$ if $R$ is ``good.'' The ``goodness'' in | |
question is to assume that $R$ is locally factorial, i.e. that | |
$R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is factorial for each $\mathfrak{p}$. This is true, for | |
instance, if $R$ is the coordinate ring of a smooth algebraic variety. | |
\begin{proposition} | |
If $R$ is locally factorial and noetherian, then the group $\cart(R)$ is a free abelian group. | |
The generators are in bijection with the height one primes of $R$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
Now assume that $R$ is a locally factorial, noetherian domain. | |
We shall produce an isomorphism | |
\[ \weil(R) \simeq \cart(R) \] | |
that sends $[\mathfrak{p}_i]$ to that height one prime $\mathfrak{p}_i$ | |
together with the imbedding $\mathfrak{p}_i \hookrightarrow R \to K(R)$. | |
We first check that this is well-defined. Since $\weil(R)$ is free, all we have | |
to do is check that each $\mathfrak{p}_i$ is a legitimate Cartier divisor. In | |
other words, we need to show that: | |
\begin{proposition} | |
If $\mathfrak{p} \subset R$ is a height one prime and $R$ locally factorial, then $\mathfrak{p}$ is | |
invertible. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
In the last lecture, we gave a criterion for invertibility: namely, being | |
locally trivial. We have to show that for any prime $\mathfrak{q}$, we have | |
that $\mathfrak{p}_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is isomorphic to $R_{\mathfrak{q}}$. If | |
$\mathfrak{p} \not\subset \mathfrak{q}$, then $\mathfrak{p}_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is | |
the entire ring $R_{\mathfrak{q}}$, so this is obvious. Conversely, suppose | |
$\mathfrak{p} \subset {\mathfrak{q}}$. Then $\mathfrak{p}_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is | |
a height one prime of $R_{\mathfrak{q}}$: it is minimal over some element in | |
$R_{\mathfrak{q}}$. | |
Thus $\mathfrak{p}_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is principal, in particular free of rank | |
one, since $R_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is factorial. We saw last time that being | |
factorial is equivalent to the principalness of height one primes. | |
\end{proof} | |
We need to define the inverse map | |
\[ \cart(R) \to \weil(R). \] | |
In order to do this, start with a Cartier divisor $(M, M \hookrightarrow | |
K(R))$. We then have to describe which coefficient to assign a height one | |
prime. To do this, we use a local criterion. | |
Let's first digress a bit. | |
Consider a locally factorial domain $R$ and a prime $\mathfrak{p}$ of height | |
one. Then $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is factorial. In particular, its maximal ideal | |
$\mathfrak{p}R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is height one, so principal. | |
It is the principal ideal generated by some $t \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. | |
Now we show: | |
\begin{proposition} | |
Every nonzero ideal in $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is of the form $(t^n)$ for some unique $n | |
\geq 0$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Let $I_0 \subset R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ be nonzero. If $I_0 = R_{\mathfrak{p}}$, then | |
we're done---it's generated by $t^0$. Otherwise, $I_0 \subsetneq | |
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$, so contained in $\mathfrak{p}R_{\mathfrak{p}} = (t)$. So let | |
$I_1 = \left\{x \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}: tx \in I_0\right\}$. Thus | |
\[ I_1 = t^{-1} I_0. \] | |
I claim now that $I_1 \neq I_0$, i.e. that there exists $x \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ such that $x | |
\notin I_0$ but $tx \in I_0$. The proof comes from the theory of associated | |
primes. | |
Look at $R_{\mathfrak{p}}/I_0$; it has at least one associated prime as it is | |
nonzero. | |
Since it | |
is a torsion module, this associated prime must be | |
$\mathfrak{p}R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ since the only primes in $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ | |
are $(0)$ and $(t)$, \textbf{which we have not yet shown}. So there exists an | |
element in the quotient $R/I_0$ whose annihilator is precisely $(t)$. Lifting | |
this gives an element in $R$ which when multiplied by $(t)$ is in $I_0$ but | |
which is not in $I_0$. So $I_0 \subsetneq I_1$. | |
Proceed as before now. Define $I_2 = \left\{x \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}: tx \in | |
I_1\right\}$. This process must halt since we have assumed noetherianness. We | |
must have $I_m = I_{m+1}$ for some $m$, which would imply that some $I_m = | |
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ by the above argument. It then follows that $I_0 = (t^m)$ | |
since each $I_i$ is just $t I_{i+1}$. | |
\end{proof} | |
We thus have a good structure theory for ideals in $R$ localized at a height one prime. | |
Let us make a more general claim. | |
\begin{proposition} | |
Every nonzero finitely generated $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$-submodule of the fraction field $K(R)$ is of the | |
form $(t^n)$ for some $n \in \mathbb{Z}$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Say that $M \subset K(R)$ is such a submodule. Let $I = \left\{x \in | |
R_{\mathfrak{p}}, x M \subset R_{\mathfrak{p}}\right\}$. Then $I \neq 0$ as $M$ | |
is finitely generated $M$ is generated over $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ by a finite number of fractions $a_i/b_i, b_i \in R$. | |
Then the product $b = \prod b_i$ brings $M$ into $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. | |
We know that $I = (t^m) $ for some $m$. In particular, $t^m M$ is an ideal in | |
$R$. In particular, | |
\[ t^m M = t^p R \] | |
for some $p$, in particular $M = t^{p-m}R$. | |
\end{proof} | |
Now let's go back to the main discussion. $R$ is a noetherian locally factorial | |
domain; we want to construct a map | |
\[ \cart(R) \to \weil(R). \] | |
Given $(M, M \hookrightarrow K(R))$ with $M$ invertible, we want to define a | |
formal sum $\sum n_i [\mathfrak{p}_i]$. For every height one prime | |
$\mathfrak{p}$, let us look at the local ring $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ with maximal | |
ideal generated by some $t_{\mathfrak{p}} \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. Now | |
$M_{\mathfrak{p}} \subset K(R)$ is a finitely generated | |
$R_{\mathfrak{p}}$-submodule, so generated by some | |
$t_{\mathfrak{p}}^{n_{\mathfrak{p}}}$. So we map $(M, M \hookrightarrow K(R))$ | |
to | |
\[ \sum_{\mathfrak{p}} n_{\mathfrak{p}}[\mathfrak{p}]. \] | |
First, we have to check that this is well-defined. In particular, we have to | |
show: | |
\begin{proposition} | |
For almost all height one $\mathfrak{p}$, we have $M_{\mathfrak{p}} = | |
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. In other words, the integers $n_{\mathfrak{p}}$ are almost all zero. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We can always assume that $M$ is actually an ideal. Indeed, choose $a \in R$ | |
with $aM = I \subset R$. As Cartier divisors, we have $M = I - (a)$. If we | |
prove the result for $I$ and $(a)$, then we will have proved it for $M$ (note | |
that the $n_{\mathfrak{p}}$'s are additive invariants\footnote{To see this, | |
localize at $\mathfrak{p}$---then if $M$ is generated by $t^a$, $N$ generated | |
by $t^b$, then $M \otimes N$ is generated by $t^{a+b}$.}). So because of this | |
additivity, it is sufficient to prove the proposition for actual (i.e. | |
nonfractional) ideals. | |
Assume thus that $M \subset R$. | |
All of these $n_{\mathfrak{p}}$ associated to $M$ are at least zero because $M$ | |
is actually an ideal. What we want is that $n_{\mathfrak{p}} \leq 0$ for almost | |
all $\mathfrak{p}$. In other words, we must show that | |
\[ M_{\mathfrak{p}} \supset R_{\mathfrak{p}} \quad \mathrm{almost \ all \ } | |
\mathfrak{p}. \] | |
To do this, just choose any $x \in M - 0$. There are finitely many minimal | |
primes containing $(x)$ (by primary decomposition applied to $R/(x)$). Every | |
other height one prime $\mathfrak{q}$ does not contain $(x)$.\footnote{Again, we're using | |
something about height one primes not proved yet.} | |
This states that $M_{\mathfrak{q}} \supset x/x = 1$, so $M_{\mathfrak{q}} | |
\supset R_{\mathfrak{q}}$. | |
The key claim we've used in this proof is the following. If $\mathfrak{q}$ is a | |
height one prime in a domain $R$ containing some nonzero element $(x)$, then | |
$\mathfrak{q}$ is minimal among primes containing $(x)$. In other words, we can | |
test the height one condition at any nonzero element in that prime. | |
Alternatively: | |
\begin{lemma} | |
There are no nontrivial containments among height one primes. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\end{proof} | |
Anyway, we have constructed maps between $\cart(R) $ and $\weil(R)$. The map | |
$\cart(R) \to \weil(R)$ takes $M \to \sum n_{\mathfrak{p}}[\mathfrak{p}]$. The | |
other map $\weil(R) \to \cart(R)$ takes $[\mathfrak{p}] \to \mathfrak{p} | |
\subset K(R)$. The composition $\weil(R) \to \weil(R)$ is the identity. Why is that? Start with a | |
prime $\mathfrak{p}$; that goes to the Cartier divisor $\mathfrak{p}$. Then we | |
need to finitely generatedre the multiplicities at other height one primes. But if | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ is height one and $\mathfrak{q}$ is a height one prime, then if | |
$\mathfrak{p} \neq \mathfrak{q}$ the lack of nontrivial containment relations | |
implies that the multiplicity of $\mathfrak{p}$ at $\mathfrak{q}$ is zero. We | |
have shown that | |
\[ \weil(R) \to \cart(R) \to \weil(R) \] | |
is the identity. | |
Now we have to show that $\cart(R) \to \weil(R)$ is injective. Say we have a | |
Cartier divisor $(M, M \hookrightarrow K(R))$ that maps to zero in $\weil(R)$, | |
i.e. all its multiplicities | |
$n_{\mathfrak{p}}$ are zero at height one primes. | |
We show that $M = R$. | |
First, assume $M \subset R$. | |
It is sufficient to show that at any maximal ideal $\mathfrak{m} \subset R$, we | |
have | |
\[ M_{\mathfrak{m}} = R_{\mathfrak{m}}. \] | |
What can we say? Well, $M_{\mathfrak{m}}$ is principal as $M$ is invertible, | |
being a Cartier divisor. Let it be generated by $x \in R_{\mathfrak{m}}$; | |
suppose $x$ is a nonunit (or we're already done). But | |
$R_{\mathfrak{m}}$ is factorial, so $x = x_1 \dots x_n$ for each $x_i $ prime. | |
If $n>0$, then however $M$ has nonzero multiplicity at the prime ideal $(x_i) \subset | |
R_{\mathfrak{m}} $. This is a contradiction. | |
The general case of $M$ not really a subset of $R$ can be handled similarly: | |
then the generating element $x$ might lie in the fraction field. So $x$, if it | |
is not a unit in $R$, is a | |
product of some primes in the numerator and some primes in the denominator. | |
The nonzero primes that occur lead to nonzero multiplicities. | |
\lecture{10/13} | |
\subsection{Recap and a loose end} | |
Last time, it was claimed that if $R$ is a locally factorial domain, and | |
$\mathfrak{p} \subset R$ is of height one, then every prime ideal of | |
$R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is either maximal or zero. This follows from general | |
dimension theory. This is equivalent to the following general claim about | |
height one primes: | |
\begin{quote} | |
There are no nontrivial inclusions among height one primes for $R$ a locally | |
factorial domain. | |
\end{quote} | |
\begin{proof} Suppose $\mathfrak{q} \subsetneq \mathfrak{p}$ is an inclusion | |
of height one primes. | |
Replace $R$ by $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. Then $R$ is local with some maximal ideal | |
$\mathfrak{m}$, which is principal with some generator $x$. | |
Then we have an inclusion | |
\[ 0 \subset \mathfrak{q} \subset \mathfrak{m}. \] | |
This inclusion is proper. However, $\mathfrak{q}$ is principal since | |
it is height one in the factorial ring $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. | |
This cannot be since every element is a power of $x$ times a unit. | |
(Alright, this wasn't live \TeX ed well.) | |
\end{proof} | |
Last time, we were talking about $\weil(R)$ and $\cart(R)$ for $R$ a locally | |
factorial noetherian domain. | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $\weil(R)$ is free on the height one primes. | |
\item $\cart(R)$ is the group of invertible submodules of $K(R)$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
We produced an isomorphism | |
\[ \weil(R) \simeq \cart(R). \] | |
\begin{remark} | |
Geometrically, what is this? Suppose $R = \mathbb{C}[X_1, \dots, X_n]/I$ for | |
some ideal $I$. Then the maximal ideals, or closed points in $\spec R$, are | |
certain points in $\mathbb{C}^n$; they form an irreducible variety if $R$ is | |
a domain. The locally factorial condition is satisfied, for instance, if the | |
variety is \emph{smooth}. In this case, the Weil divisors correspond to sums of | |
irreducible varieties of codimension one---which correspond to the primes of | |
height one. The Weil divisors are free on the set | |
of irreducible varieties of codimension one. | |
The Cartier divisors can be thought of as ``linear combinations'' of | |
subvarieties which are locally defined by one equation. It is natural to assume | |
that the condition of being defined by one equation corresponds to being | |
codimension one. This is true by the condition of $R$ locally factorial. | |
In general, we can always construct a map | |
\[ \cart(R) \to \weil(R), \] | |
but it is not necessarily an isomorphism. | |
\end{remark} | |
\subsection{Further remarks on $\weil(R)$ and $\cart(R)$} Recall that the Cartier group fits in an exact sequence: | |
\[ K(R)^* \to \cart(R) \to \pic(R) \to 0, \] | |
because every element of $\cart(R)$ determines its isomorphism class, and | |
every element of $K(R)^*$ determines a free module of rank one. Contrary | |
to what was stated last time, it is \textbf{not true} that exactness holds on | |
the right. In fact, the kernel is the group $R^*$ of units of $R$. So the exact | |
sequence runs | |
\[ 0 \to R^* \to K(R)^* \to \cart(R) \to \pic(R) \to 0. \] | |
This is true for \emph{any} domain $R$. For $R$ locally factorial and | |
noetherian, we know that $\cart(R) \simeq \weil(R)$, though. | |
We can think of this as a generalization of unique factorization. | |
\begin{proposition} | |
$R$ is factorial if and only if $R$ is locally factorial and $\pic(R) = 0$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Assume $R$ is locally factorial and $\pic(R)=0$. Then every prime ideal of | |
height one (an element of $\weil(R)$, hence of $\cart(R)$) is principal, which | |
implies that $R$ is factorial. And conversely. | |
\end{proof} | |
In general, we can think of the exact sequence above as a form of unique | |
factorization for a locally factorial domain: any invertible fractional ideal is a product of height one prime | |
ideals. | |
Let us now give an example. | |
\add{?} | |