Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
\titleformat{\chapter}[display]{\fontsize{23}{25}\fontseries{m}\fontshape{it}\selectfont}{\chaptertitlename}{20pt}{\fontsize{35}{35}\fontseries{b}\fontshape{n}\selectfont} | |
\chapter{Formal type theory} | |
\label{cha:rules} | |
\index{formal!type theory|(}% | |
\index{type theory!formal|(}% | |
\index{rules of type theory|(}% | |
Just as one can develop mathematics in set theory without explicitly using the axioms of Zermelo--Fraenkel set theory, | |
in this book we have developed mathematics in univalent foundations without explicitly referring to a formal | |
system of homotopy type theory. Nevertheless, it is important to \emph{have} a | |
precise description of homotopy type theory as a formal system in order to, for example, | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item state and prove its metatheoretic properties, including logical | |
consistency, | |
\item construct models, e.g.\ in simplicial sets, model categories, higher toposes, | |
etc., and | |
\item implement it in proof assistants like \Coq or \Agda. | |
\index{proof!assistant} | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
Even the logical consistency\index{consistency} of homotopy type theory, namely that in the empty context there is no term $a:\emptyt$, is not obvious: if we had erroneously | |
chosen a definition of equivalence for which $\eqv{\emptyt}{\unit}$, then | |
univalence would imply that $\emptyt$ has an element, since $\unit$ does. | |
Nor is it obvious that, for example, our definition of $\Sn^1$ as a higher | |
inductive type yields a type which behaves like the ordinary circle. | |
There are two aspects of type theory which we must pin down before addressing | |
such questions. Recall from the Introduction that type theory | |
comprises a set of rules specifying when the judgments $a:A$ and $a\jdeq a':A$ | |
hold---for example, products are characterized by the rule that whenever $a:A$ | |
and $b:B$, $(a,b):A\times B$. To make this precise, we must first define | |
precisely the syntax of terms---the objects $a,a',A,\dots$ which these judgments | |
relate; then, we must define precisely the judgments and their rules of | |
inference---the manner in which judgments can be derived from other judgments. | |
In this appendix, we present two formulations of Martin-L\"{o}f type | |
theory, and of the extensions that constitute homotopy type theory. | |
The first presentation (\cref{sec:syntax-informally}) describes the syntax of | |
terms and the forms of judgments as an extension of the untyped | |
$\lambda$-calculus, while leaving the rules of inference informal. | |
The second (\cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}) defines the terms, judgments, | |
and rules of inference inductively in the style of natural deduction, as | |
is customary in much type-theoretic literature. | |
\section*{Preliminaries} | |
\label{sec:formal-prelim} | |
In \cref{cha:typetheory}, we presented the two basic \define{judgments} | |
\index{judgment} | |
of type theory. The first, $a:A$, asserts that a term $a$ has type $A$. The second, | |
$a\jdeq b:A$, states that the two terms $a$ and $b$ are \define{judgmentally | |
equal}% | |
\index{equality!judgmental} | |
\index{judgmental equality} | |
at type $A$. These judgments are inductively defined by a set of | |
inference rules described in \cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}. | |
To construct an element $a$ of a type $A$ is to derive $a:A$; in the book, we | |
give informal arguments which describe the construction of $a$, but formally, | |
one must specify a precise term $a$ and a full derivation that $a:A$. | |
However, the main difference between the presentation of type theory in the book | |
and in this appendix is that here judgments are explicitly | |
formulated in an ambient \define{context}, | |
\index{context} | |
or list of assumptions, of the form | |
\[ | |
x_1:A_1, x_2:A_2,\dots,x_n:A_n. | |
\] | |
An element $x_i : A_i$ of the context expresses the assumption that the | |
variable | |
\index{variable}% | |
$x_i$ has type $A_i$. The variables $x_1, \ldots, x_n$ appearing in | |
the context must be distinct. We abbreviate contexts with the letters $\Gamma$ | |
and $\Delta$. | |
The judgment $a:A$ in context $\Gamma$ is written | |
\[ \oftp\Gamma aA \] | |
and means that $a:A$ under the assumptions listed in $\Gamma$. When the list of | |
assumptions is empty, we write simply | |
\[ \oftp{}aA \] | |
or | |
\[ \oftp\emptyctx aA \] | |
where $\emptyctx$ denotes the empty context. The same applies to the equality | |
judgment | |
\[ | |
\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A} | |
\] | |
However, such judgments are sensible only for \define{well-formed} contexts, | |
\index{context!well-formed}% | |
a notion captured by our third and final judgment | |
\[ | |
\wfctx{(x_1:A_1, x_2:A_2,\dots,x_n:A_n)} | |
\] | |
expressing that each $A_i$ is a type in the context $x_1:A_1, | |
x_2:A_2,\dots,x_{i-1}:A_{i-1}$. In particular, therefore, if $\oftp\Gamma aA$ and | |
$\wfctx\Gamma$, then we know that each $A_i$ contains only the variables | |
$x_1,\dots,x_{i-1}$, and that $a$ and $A$ contain only the variables | |
$x_1,\dots,x_n$. | |
\index{variable!in context} | |
In informal mathematical presentations, the context is | |
implicit. At each point in a proof, the mathematician knows which | |
variables are available and what types they have, either by historical | |
convention ($n$ is usually a number, $f$ is a function, etc.) or | |
because variables are explicitly introduced with sentences such as | |
``let $x$ be a real number''. We discuss some benefits of using explicit | |
contexts in \cref{sec:more-formal-pi,sec:more-formal-sigma}. | |
We write $B[a/x]$ for the \define{substitution} | |
\index{substitution}% | |
of a term $a$ for free occurrences of | |
the variable~$x$ in the term $B$, with possible capture-avoiding | |
renaming of bound variables, | |
\index{variable!and substitution}% | |
as discussed in | |
\cref{sec:function-types}. The general form of substitution | |
% | |
\[ | |
B[a_1,\dots,a_n/x_1,\dots,x_n] | |
\] | |
% | |
substitutes expressions $a_1,\dots,a_n$ for the variables | |
$x_1,\dots,x_n$ simultaneously. | |
To \define{bind a variable $x$ in an expression $B$} | |
\indexdef{variable!bound}% | |
means to incorporate both of them into a larger expression, called an \define{abstraction}, | |
\indexdef{abstraction}% | |
whose purpose is to express the fact that $x$ is ``local'' to $B$, i.e., it | |
is not to be confused with other occurrences of $x$ appearing | |
elsewhere. Bound variables are familiar to programmers, but less so to mathematicians. | |
Various notations are used for binding, such as $x \mapsto B$, | |
$\lam x B$, and $x \,.\, B$, depending on the situation. We may write $C[a]$ for the | |
substitution of a term $a$ for the variable in the abstracted expression, i.e., | |
we may define $(x.B)[a]$ to be $B[a/x]$. As discussed in | |
\cref{sec:function-types}, changing the name of a bound variable everywhere within an expression (``$\alpha$-conversion'') | |
\index{alpha-conversion@$\alpha $-conversion}% | |
does not change the expression. Thus, to be very | |
precise, an expression is an equivalence class of syntactic forms | |
which differ in names of bound variables. | |
One may also regard each variable $x_i$ of a judgment | |
\[ | |
x_1:A_1, x_2:A_2,\dots,x_n:A_n \vdash a : A | |
\] | |
to be bound in its \define{scope}, | |
\indexdef{variable!scope of}% | |
\index{scope}% | |
consisting of the expressions $A_{i+1}, | |
\ldots, A_n$, $a$, and $A$. | |
\section{The first presentation} | |
\label{sec:syntax-informally} | |
The objects and types of our type theory may be written as terms using | |
the following syntax, which is an extension of $\lambda$-calculus with | |
\emph{variables} $x, x',\dots$, | |
\index{variable}% | |
\emph{primitive constants} | |
\index{primitive!constant}% | |
\index{constant!primitive}% | |
$c,c',\dots$, \emph{defined constants}\index{constant!defined} $f,f',\dots$, and term forming | |
operations | |
% | |
\[ | |
t \production x \mid \lam{x} t \mid t(t') \mid c \mid f | |
\] | |
% | |
The notation used here means that a term $t$ is either a variable $x$, or it | |
has the form $\lam{x} t$ where $x$ is a variable and $t$ is a term, or it has | |
the form $t(t')$ where $t$ and $t'$ are terms, or it is a primitive constant | |
$c$, or it is a defined constant $f$. The syntactic markers '$\lambda$', '(', | |
')', and '.' are punctuation for guiding the human eye. | |
We use $t(t_1,\dots,t_n)$ as an abbreviation for the repeated application | |
$t(t_1)(t_2)\dots (t_n)$. We may also use \emph{infix}\index{infix notation} notation, writing $t_1\; | |
\star\; t_2$ for $\star(t_1,t_2)$ when $\star$ is a primitive or defined | |
constant. | |
Each defined constant has zero, one or more \define{defining equations}. | |
\index{equation, defining}% | |
\index{defining equation}% | |
There are two kinds of defined constant. An \emph{explicit} | |
\index{constant!explicit} | |
defined constant $f$ has a single defining equation | |
\[ f(x_1,\dots,x_n)\defeq t,\] | |
where $t$ does not involve $f$. | |
% | |
For example, we might introduce the explicit defined constant $\circ$ with defining equation | |
\[ \circ (x,y)(z) \defeq x(y(z)),\] | |
and use infix notation $x\circ y$ for $\circ(x,y)$. This of course is just composition of functions. | |
The second kind of defined constant is used to specify a (parameterized) mapping | |
$f(x_1,\dots,x_n,x)$, where $x$ ranges over a type whose elements are generated | |
by zero or more primitive constants. For each such primitive constant $c$ there | |
is a defining equation of the form | |
\[ | |
f(x_1,\dots,x_n,c(y_1,\dots,y_m)) \defeq t, | |
\] | |
where $f$ may occur in $t$, but only in such a way that it is clear that the | |
equations determine a totally defined function. The paradigm examples of such | |
defined functions are the functions defined by primitive recursion on the | |
natural numbers. We may call this kind of definition of a function a \emph{total | |
recursive definition}. | |
\index{total!recursive definition}% | |
In computer science and logic this kind of definition | |
of a function on a recursive data type has been called a \define{definition by | |
structural recursion}. | |
\index{definition!by structural recursion}% | |
\index{structural!recursion}% | |
\index{recursion!structural}% | |
\define{Convertibility} | |
\index{convertibility of terms}% | |
\index{term!convertibility of}% | |
$t \conv t'$ between terms $t$ | |
and $t'$ is the equivalence relation generated by the defining equations for constants, | |
the computation rule\index{computation rule!for function types} | |
% | |
\[ | |
(\lam{x} t)(u) \defeq t[u/x], | |
\] | |
% | |
and the rules which make it a \emph{congruence} with respect to application and $\lambda$-abstraction\index{lambda abstraction@$\lambda$-abstraction}: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $t \conv t'$ and $s \conv s'$ then $t(s) \conv t'(s')$, and | |
\item if $t \conv t'$ then $(\lam{x} t) \conv (\lam{x} t')$. | |
\end{itemize} | |
\noindent | |
The equality judgment $t \jdeq u : A$ is then derived by the following single rule: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $t:A$, $u:A$, and $t \conv u$, then $t \jdeq u : A$. | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
Judgmental equality is an equivalence relation. | |
Note that the type theory of this presentation diverges from that used in the main body of the text in not including the judgmental uniqueness principle $f \jdeq (\lam{x} f(x))$ for functions. | |
Such an equality requires that judgmental equality be sensitive to the type of the terms involved, as this equality only makes sense when $f$ is known to be a function, whereas in this presentation the convertibility relation is type-independent. | |
The second presentation in \cref{sec:syntax-more-formally} includes the uniqueness principle. | |
\subsection{Type universes} | |
We postulate a hierarchy of \define{universes} denoted by primitive constants | |
\index{type!universe} | |
% | |
\begin{equation*} | |
\UU_0, \quad \UU_1, \quad \UU_2, \quad \ldots | |
\end{equation*} | |
% | |
The first two rules for universes say that they form a cumulative hierarchy of types: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item $\UU_m : \UU_n$ for $m < n$, | |
\item if $A:\UU_m$ and $m \le n$, then $A:\UU_n$, | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
and the third expresses the idea that an object of a universe can serve as a type and stand to the | |
right of a colon in judgments: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $\Gamma \vdash A : \UU_n$, and $x$ is a new variable,% | |
\footnote{By ``new'' we mean that it does not appear in $\Gamma$ or $A$.} | |
then $\vdash (\Gamma, x:A)\; \ctx$. | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
In the body of the book, an equality judgment $A \jdeq B : \UU_n$ between types | |
$A$ and $B$ is usually abbreviated to $A \jdeq B$. This is an instance of | |
typical ambiguity\index{typical ambiguity}, as we can always switch to a larger universe, which however does not affect the validity of the judgment. | |
The following conversion rule allows us to replace a type by one equal to it in a typing judgment: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $a:A$ and $A \jdeq B$ then $a:B$. | |
\end{itemize} | |
\subsection{Dependent function types (\texorpdfstring{$\Pi$}{Π}-types)} | |
We introduce a primitive constant $c_\Pi$, but write | |
$c_\Pi(A,\lam{x} B)$ as $\tprd{x:A}B$. Judgments concerning | |
such expressions and expressions of the form $\lam{x} b$ are introduced by the following rules: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $\Gamma \vdash A:\UU_n$ and $\Gamma,x:A \vdash B:\UU_n$, then $\Gamma \vdash \tprd{x:A}B : \UU_n$ | |
\item if $\Gamma, x:A \vdash b:B$ then $\Gamma \vdash (\lam{x} b) : (\tprd{x:A} B)$ | |
\item if $\Gamma\vdash g:\tprd{x:A} B$ and $\Gamma\vdash t:A$ then $\Gamma\vdash g(t):B[t/x]$ | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
If $x$ does not occur freely in $B$, we abbreviate $\tprd{x:A} B$ as the non-dependent function type | |
$A\rightarrow B$ and derive the following rule: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $\Gamma\vdash g:A \rightarrow B$ and $\Gamma\vdash t:A$ then $\Gamma\vdash g(t):B$ | |
\end{itemize} | |
Using non-dependent function types and leaving implicit the context $\Gamma$, the rules above can be written in the following alternative style that we use in the rest of this section of the appendix: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $A:\UU_n$ and $B:A\to\UU_n$, then $\tprd{x:A}B(x) : \UU_n$ | |
\item if $x:A \vdash b:B(x)$ then $ \lam{x} b : \tprd{x:A} B(x)$ | |
\item if $g:\tprd{x:A} B(x)$ and $t:A$ then $g(t):B(t)$ | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
\subsection{Dependent pair types (\texorpdfstring{$\Sigma$}{Σ}-types)} | |
We introduce primitive constants $c_\Sigma$ and $c_{\mathsf{pair}}$. An | |
expression of the form $c_\Sigma(A,\lam{a} B)$ is written as $\sm{a:A}B$, | |
and an expression of the form $c_{\mathsf{pair}}(a,b)$ is written as $\tup | |
a b$. We write $A\times B$ instead of $\sm{x:A} B$ if $x$ is not free in $B$. | |
Judgments concerning such expressions are introduced by the following | |
rules: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $A:\UU_n$ and $B: A \rightarrow \UU_n$, then $\sm{x:A}B(x) : \UU_n$ | |
\item if, in addition, $a:A$ and $b:B(a)$, then $\tup a b:\sm{x:A}B(x)$ | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
If we have $A$ and $B$ as above, $C : (\sm{x:A}B(x)) \rightarrow \UU_m$, and | |
\[ | |
d:\tprd{x:A}{y:B(x)} C(\tup x y) | |
\] | |
we can introduce a defined constant | |
\[ | |
f:\tprd{p:\sm{x:A}B(x)} C(p) | |
\] | |
with the defining equation | |
\[ | |
f(\tup x y)\defeq d(x,y). | |
\] | |
% | |
Note that $C$, $d$, $x$, and $y$ may contain extra implicit parameters $x_1,\ldots,x_n$ if they were obtained in some non-empty context; therefore, the fully explicit recursion schema is | |
% | |
\begin{narrowmultline*} | |
f(x_1,\dots,x_n,\tup{x(x_1,\dots,x_n)}{y(x_1,\dots,x_n)}) \defeq | |
\narrowbreak | |
d(x_1,\dots,x_n,\tup{x(x_1,\dots,x_n)}{y(x_1,\dots,x_n)}). | |
\end{narrowmultline*} | |
\subsection{Coproduct types} | |
We introduce primitive constants $c_+$, $c_\inlsym$, and $c_\inrsym$. | |
We write $A+B$ instead of $c_+(A,B)$, $\inl(a)$ instead of | |
$c_\inlsym(a)$, and $\inr(a)$ instead of $c_\inrsym(a)$: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $A,B : \UU_n$ then $A + B : \UU_n$ | |
\item moreover, $\inl: A \rightarrow A+B$ and $\inr: B \rightarrow A+B$ | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
If we have $A$ and $B$ as above, $C : A+B \rightarrow \UU_m$, | |
$d:\tprd{x:A} C(\inl(x))$, and $e:\tprd{y:B} C(\inr(y))$, | |
then we can introduce a defined constant $f:\tprd{z:A+B}C(z)$ with the defining equations | |
% | |
\begin{equation*} | |
f(\inl(x)) \defeq d(x) | |
\qquad\text{and}\qquad | |
f(\inr(y)) \defeq e(y). | |
\end{equation*} | |
\subsection{The finite types} | |
We introduce primitive constants $\ttt$, $\emptyt$, $\unit$, satisfying the following rules: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item $\emptyt : \UU_0$, $\unit : \UU_0$ | |
\item $\ttt:\unit$ | |
\end{itemize} | |
Given $C : \emptyt \rightarrow \UU_n$ we can introduce a defined constant $f:\tprd{x:\emptyt} C(x)$, with no defining equations. | |
Given $C : \unit \rightarrow \UU_n$ and $d : C(\ttt)$ we can introduce a defined constant $f:\tprd{x:\unit} C(x)$, with defining equation $f(\ttt) \defeq d$. | |
\subsection{Natural numbers} | |
The type of natural numbers is obtained by introducing primitive constants | |
$\N$, $0$, and $\suc$ with the following rules: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item $\N : \UU_0$, | |
\item $0:\N$, | |
\item $\suc:\N\rightarrow \N$. | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
Furthermore, we can define functions by primitive recursion. If we have | |
$C : \N \rightarrow \UU_k $ we can introduce a defined constant $f:\tprd{x:\N}C(x)$ whenever we have | |
% | |
\begin{align*} | |
d & : C(0) \\ | |
e & : \tprd{x:\N}(C(x)\rightarrow C(\suc (x))) | |
\end{align*} | |
% | |
with the defining equations | |
% | |
\begin{equation*} | |
f(0) \defeq d | |
\qquad\text{and}\qquad | |
f(\suc (x)) \defeq e(x,f(x)). | |
\end{equation*} | |
\subsection{\texorpdfstring{$W$}{W}-types} | |
For $W$-types we introduce primitive constants $c_\wtypesym$ and $c_\suppsym$. | |
An expression of the form $c_\wtypesym(A,\lam{x} B)$ is written as | |
$\wtype{x:A}B$, and an expression of the form $c_\suppsym(x,u)$ is written | |
as $\supp(x,u)$: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item if $A:\UU_n$ and $B: A \rightarrow \UU_n$, then $\wtype{x:A}B(x) : \UU_n$ | |
\item if moreover, $a:A$ and $u:B(a)\rightarrow \wtype{x:A}B(x)$ then $\supp(a,u):\wtype{x:A}B(x)$. | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
Here also we can define functions by total recursion. If we have $A$ and $B$ | |
as above and $C : (\wtype{x:A}B(x)) \rightarrow \UU_m$, then we can introduce a defined constant | |
$f:\tprd{z:\wtype{x:A}B(x)} C(z)$ whenever we have | |
\[ | |
d:\tprd{a:A}{u:B(a) \rightarrow \wtype{x:A}B(x)}((\tprd{y:B(a)}C(u(y))) \rightarrow C(\supp(a,u))) | |
\] | |
with the defining equation | |
\[ | |
f(\supp(a,u)) \defeq d(a,u,f\circ u). | |
\] | |
\subsection{Identity types} | |
We introduce primitive constants $c_\idsym$ and $c_{\refl{}}$. We write | |
$\id[A] a b$ for $c_\idsym(A,a,b)$ and $\refl a$ for $c_{\refl{}}(A,a)$, when | |
$a:A$ is understood: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item If $A : \UU_n$, $a:A$, and $b:A$ then $\id[A] a b : \UU_n$. | |
\item If $a:A$ then $\refl a :\id[A] a a $. | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
Given $a:A$, if $y:A, z:\id[A] a y \vdash C : \UU_m$ and | |
$\vdash d:C[a,\refl{a}/y,z]$ then we can introduce a defined constant | |
\[ | |
f:\tprd{y:A}{z:\id[A] a y} C | |
\] | |
with defining equation | |
\[ | |
f(a,\refl{a})\defeq d. | |
\] | |
\section{The second presentation} | |
\label{sec:syntax-more-formally} | |
In this section, there are three kinds of judgments | |
\begin{mathpar} | |
\wfctx\Gamma | |
\and | |
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} | |
\and | |
\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{a'}{A} | |
\end{mathpar} | |
which we specify by providing inference rules for deriving them. A typical \define{inference rule} | |
\indexsee{inference rule}{rule}% | |
\indexdef{rule}% | |
has the form | |
% | |
\begin{equation*} | |
\inferrule*[right=\textsc{Name}] | |
{\mathcal{J}_1 \\ \cdots \\ \mathcal{J}_k} | |
{\mathcal{J}} | |
\end{equation*} | |
% | |
It says that we may derive the \define{conclusion} $\mathcal{J}$, provided that we have | |
already derived the \define{hypotheses} $\mathcal{J}_1, \ldots, \mathcal{J}_k$. | |
(Note that, being judgments rather than types, these are not hypotheses \emph{internal} to the type theory in the sense of \cref{sec:types-vs-sets}; they are instead hypotheses in the deductive system, i.e.\ the metatheory.) | |
On the | |
right we write the \textsc{Name} of the rule, and there may be extra side conditions that | |
need to be checked before the rule is applicable. | |
A \define{derivation} | |
\index{derivation}% | |
of a judgment is a tree constructed from such inference | |
rules, with the judgment at the root of the tree. For example, with the rules given below, the following is a derivation of | |
$\oftp{\emptyctx}{\lamu{x:\unit} x}{\unit\to\unit}$. | |
% | |
\begin{mathpar} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\rintro] | |
{\inferrule*[right=$\Vble$] | |
{\inferrule*[right=\ctx-\textsc{ext}] | |
{\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\rform] | |
{\inferrule*[right=\ctx-\textsc{emp}] | |
{\ } | |
{\wfctx {\emptyctx}}} | |
{\oftp{}{\unit}{\UU_0}}} | |
{\wfctx {\tmtp x\unit}}} | |
{\oftp{\tmtp x\unit}{x}{\unit}}} | |
{\oftp{\emptyctx}{\lamu{x:\unit} x}{\unit\to\unit}} | |
\end{mathpar} | |
\subsection{Contexts} | |
\label{subsec:contexts} | |
\index{context}% | |
A context is a list | |
% | |
\begin{equation*} | |
\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \tmtp{x_2}{A_2}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n} | |
\end{equation*} | |
% | |
which indicates that the distinct variables | |
\index{variable}% | |
$x_1, \ldots, x_n$ are assumed to have types $A_1, \ldots, A_n$, respectively. The list may be empty. We abbreviate contexts with the letters $\Gamma$ and $\Delta$, and we may juxtapose them to form larger contexts. | |
The judgment $\wfctx{\Gamma}$ formally expresses the fact that $\Gamma$ is a well-formed context, and is governed by the rules of inference | |
% | |
\begin{mathpar} | |
\inferrule*[right=\ctx-\textsc{emp}] | |
{\ } | |
{\wfctx\emptyctx} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=\ctx-\textsc{ext}] | |
{\oftp{\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_{n-1}}{A_{n-1}}}{A_n}{\UU_i}} | |
{\wfctx{(\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n})}} | |
\end{mathpar} | |
% | |
with a side condition for the second rule: the variable $x_n$ must be distinct from the variables $x_1, \ldots, x_{n-1}$. | |
Note that the hypothesis and conclusion of $\ctx$-\textsc{ext} are judgments of different forms: the hypothesis says that in the context of variables $x_1, \ldots, x_{n-1}$, the expression $A_n$ has type $\UU_i$; while the conclusion says that the extended context $(\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n})$ is well-formed. | |
It is a meta-theoretic property of the system that if any judgment of the form $\oftp{\Gamma}{a}{A}$ or $\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{a'}{A}$ is derivable, then so is the judgment $\wfctx\Gamma$ that the context $\Gamma$ is well-formed. | |
The premises of all the rules are chosen to include just enough well-formedness hypotheses to make this property provable, but no more. | |
For instance, it is not necessary for $\ctx$-\textsc{ext} to hypothesize well-formedness of $(\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_{n-1}}{A_{n-1}})$, as that will follow from the derivability of its premise; but it is necessary for the $\Vble$ rule in the next section to hypothesize well-formedness of its context. | |
This choice is only one of the many possible ways to formulate a type theory precisely, but a detailed investigation of such issues is beyond the scope of this appendix. | |
\subsection{Structural rules} | |
\index{structural!rules|(}% | |
\index{rule!structural|(}% | |
The fact that the context holds assumptions is expressed by the rule which says that we may derive those typing judgments which are listed in the context: | |
% | |
\begin{mathpar} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Vble$] | |
{\wfctx {(\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n})} } | |
{\oftp{\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n}}{x_i}{A_i}} | |
\end{mathpar} | |
% | |
As with $\ctx$-\textsc{ext}, the hypothesis and conclusion of the rule $\Vble$ are judgments of different forms, only now they are reversed: we start with a well-formed context and derive a typing judgment. | |
The following important principles, called \define{substitution} | |
\indexdef{rule!of substitution}% | |
and | |
\define{weakening}, | |
\indexdef{rule!of weakening}% | |
need not be explicitly assumed. Rather, it is possible to | |
show, by induction on the structure of all possible derivations, that whenever | |
the hypotheses of these rules are derivable, their conclusion is also | |
derivable.\footnote{Such rules are called \define{admissible}\indexdef{rule!admissible}\indexsee{admissible!rule}{rule, admissible}.} | |
For the typing judgments these principles are manifested as | |
% | |
\begin{mathpar} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Subst_1$] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\Delta}{b}{B}} | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\Delta[a/x]}{b[a/x]}{B[a/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Weak_1$] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp{\Gamma,\Delta}{b}{B}} | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\Delta}{b}{B}} | |
\end{mathpar} | |
and for judgmental equalities they become | |
\begin{mathpar} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Subst_2$] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \jdeqtp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\Delta}{b}{c}{B}} | |
{\jdeqtp{\Gamma,\Delta[a/x]}{b[a/x]}{c[a/x]}{B[a/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Subst_3$] | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A} \\ \oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\Delta}{c}{C}} | |
{\jdeqtp{\Gamma,\Delta[a/x]}{c[a/x]}{c[b/x]}{C[a/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Weak_2$] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \jdeqtp{\Gamma,\Delta}{b}{c}{B}} | |
{\jdeqtp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\Delta}{b}{c}{B}} | |
\end{mathpar} | |
% | |
In addition to the judgmental equality rules given for each type former, we also | |
assume that judgmental equality is an equivalence relation respected by typing. | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\inferrule*{\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}}{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{a}{A}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A}}{\jdeqtp\Gamma{b}{a}{A}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A} \\ \jdeqtp\Gamma{b}{c}{A}}{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{c}{A}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*{\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \jdeqtp\Gamma{A}{B}{\UU_i}}{\oftp\Gamma{a}{B}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A} \\ \jdeqtp\Gamma{A}{B}{\UU_i}}{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{B}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
Finally, we assume that judgmental equality is a congruence respected by typing, | |
i.e., that each type and term-former preserves judgmental equality in each of | |
its arguments. For instance, along with the $\Pi$-\rintro\ rule, we assume the | |
rule | |
\[ | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\rintro-eq] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{B}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\jdeqtp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{b}{b'}{B}} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\lamu{x:A} b}{\lamu{x:A'} b'}{\tprd{x:A} B}} | |
\] | |
Completing the case of dependent function types, two similar rules, | |
$\Pi$-\textsc{form-eq}\ and $\Pi$-\textsc{elim-eq}, are assumed. | |
Taken together, these local principles (at every type) imply the global congruence principles | |
$\Subst_2$ and $\Subst_3$ above. We will omit these local rules for brevity. | |
\index{rule!structural|)}% | |
\index{structural!rules|)}% | |
\subsection{Type universes} | |
\index{type!universe}% | |
We postulate an infinite hierarchy of type universes | |
% | |
\begin{equation*} | |
\UU_0, \quad \UU_1, \quad \UU_2, \quad \ldots | |
\end{equation*} | |
% | |
Each universe is contained in the next, and any type in $\UU_i$ is also in $\UU_{i+1}$: | |
% | |
\begin{mathpar} | |
\inferrule*[right=\UU-\textsc{intro}] | |
{\wfctx \Gamma } | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\UU_i}{\UU_{i+1}}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=\UU-\textsc{cumul}] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_{i+1}}} | |
\end{mathpar} | |
% | |
We shall set up the rules of type theory in such a way that $\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}$ | |
implies $\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i}$ for some $i$. In other words, if $A$ plays the role of a type then it is in some universe. Another property of our type system is that $\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A}$ | |
implies $\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}$ and $\oftp\Gamma{b}{A}$. | |
\subsection{Dependent function types (\texorpdfstring{$\Pi$}{Π}-types)} | |
\label{sec:more-formal-pi} | |
\index{type!dependent function}% | |
\index{type!function}% | |
In \cref{sec:function-types}, we introduced non-dependent functions $A\to B$ in | |
order to define a family of types as a function $\lam{x:A} B:A\to\UU_i$, which | |
then gives rise to a type of dependent functions $\tprd{x:A} B$. But with explicit contexts | |
we may replace $\lam{x:A} B:A\to\UU_i$ with the judgment | |
% | |
\begin{equation*} | |
\oftp{\tmtp xA}{B}{\UU_i}. | |
\end{equation*} | |
% | |
Consequently, we may define dependent functions directly, without reference to non-dependent ones. This way we follow the general principle that each type former, with its constants and rules, should be introduced independently of all other type formers. | |
% | |
In fact, henceforth each type former is introduced systematically by: | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item a \define{formation rule}, stating when the type former can be applied;\index{formation rule}\index{rule!formation} | |
\item some \define{introduction rules}, stating how to inhabit the type;\index{introduction rule}\index{rule!introduction} | |
\item \define{elimination rules}, or an induction principle, stating how to use an | |
element of the type; | |
\index{induction principle}\index{eliminator} | |
\item \define{computation rules}, which are judgmental equalities explaining what happens when elimination rules are applied to results of introduction rules; | |
\index{computation rule} | |
\indexsee{rule!computation}{computation rule} | |
\item optional \define{uniqueness principles}, which are judgmental equalities explaining how every element of the type is uniquely determined by the results of elimination rules applied to it. | |
\index{uniqueness!principle} | |
\indexsee{principle!uniqueness}{uniqueness principle} | |
\end{itemize} | |
(See also \cref{rmk:introducing-new-concepts}.) | |
For the dependent function type these rules are: | |
% | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\def\premise{\oftp{\Gamma}{A}{\UU_i} \and \oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{B}{\UU_i}} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\rform] | |
\premise | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\tprd{x:A}B}{\UU_i}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\rintro] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{b}{B}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\lam{x:A} b}{\tprd{x:A} B}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\relim] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{f}{\tprd{x:A} B} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{f(a)}{B[a/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\rcomp] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{b}{B} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A}} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{(\lam{x:A} b)(a)}{b[a/x]}{B[a/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\runiq] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{f}{\tprd{x:A} B}} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{f}{(\lamu{x:A}f(x))}{\tprd{x:A} B}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
The expression $\lam{x:A} b$ binds free occurrences of $x$ in $b$, as does $\tprd{x:A} B$ for | |
$B$. | |
When $x$ does not occur freely in $B$ so that $B$ does not depend on $A$, we obtain as a | |
special case the ordinary function type $A\to B \defeq \tprd{x:A} B$. We take this as the \emph{definition} of $\to$. | |
We may abbreviate an expression $\lam{x:A} b$ as $\lamu{x:A} b$, with the understanding | |
that the omitted type $A$ should be filled in appropriately before type-checking. | |
\subsection{Dependent pair types (\texorpdfstring{$\Sigma$}{Σ}-types)} | |
\label{sec:more-formal-sigma} | |
\index{type!dependent pair}% | |
\index{type!product}% | |
In \cref{sec:sigma-types}, we needed $\to$ and $\prdsym$ types in order to | |
define the introduction and elimination rules for $\smsym$; as with $\prdsym$, contexts allow us to state the rules for $\smsym$ independently. | |
Recall that the elimination rule for a positive type such as $\Sigma$ is called \emph{induction} and denoted by $\ind{}$. | |
% | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\def\premise{\oftp{\Gamma}{A}{\UU_i} \and \oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{B}{\UU_i}} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sigma$-\rform] | |
\premise | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\tsm{x:A} B}{\UU_i}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sigma$-\rintro] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma, \tmtp x A}{B}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{b}{B[a/x]}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\tup ab}{\tsm{x:A} B}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sigma$-\relim] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma, \tmtp z {\tsm{x:A} B}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x A,\tmtp y B}{g}{C[\tup x y/z]} \\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{p}{\tsm{x:A} B}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}(z.C,x.y.g,p)}{C[p/z]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sigma$-\rcomp] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma, \tmtp z {\tsm{x:A} B}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma, \tmtp x A, \tmtp y B}{g}{C[\tup x y/z]} \\\\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{b}{B[a/x]}} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}(z.C,x.y.g,\tup{a}{b})}{g[a,b/x,y]}{C[\tup {a} {b}/z]}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
The expression $\tsm{x:A} B$ binds free occurrences of $x$ in $B$. Furthermore, because | |
$\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}$ has some arguments with free variables beyond those in $\Gamma$, | |
we bind (following the variable names above) $z$ in $C$, and $x$ and $y$ in $g$. | |
These bindings are written as $z.C$ and $x.y.g$, to indicate the names of the bound | |
variables. | |
\index{variable!bound}% | |
In particular, we treat $\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}$ as a primitive, | |
two of whose arguments contain binders; this is superficially similar to, but | |
different from, $\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}$ being a function that takes functions as | |
arguments. | |
When $B$ does not contain free occurrences of $x$, we obtain as a special case | |
the cartesian product $A \times B \defeq \tsm{x:A} B$. We take this | |
as the \emph{definition} of the cartesian product. | |
Notice that we don't postulate a judgmental uniqueness principle for $\Sigma$-types, even | |
though we could have; see \cref{thm:eta-sigma} for a proof of the corresponding | |
propositional uniqueness principle. | |
\subsection{Coproduct types} | |
\index{type!coproduct}% | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\rform] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{B}{\UU_i}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A+B}{\UU_i}} | |
\\ | |
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\rintro${}_1$] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{B}{\UU_i} \\\\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\inl(a)}{A+B}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\rintro${}_2$] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{B}{\UU_i} \\\\ \oftp\Gamma{b}{B}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\inr(b)}{A+B}} | |
\\ | |
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\relim] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp z{(A+B)}}{C}{\UU_i} \\\\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{c}{C[\inl(x)/z]} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp yB}{d}{C[\inr(y)/z]} \\\\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{e}{A+B}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{A+B}(z.C,x.c,y.d,e)}{C[e/z]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\rcomp${}_1$] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp z{(A+B)}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{c}{C[\inl(x)/z]} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp yB}{d}{C[\inr(y)/z]} \\\\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{A+B}(z.C,x.c,y.d,\inl(a))}{c[a/x]}{C[\inl(a)/z]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\rcomp${}_2$] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp z{(A+B)}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{c}{C[\inl(x)/z]} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp yB}{d}{C[\inr(y)/z]} \\\\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{b}{B}} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{A+B}(z.C,x.c,y.d,\inr(b))}{d[b/y]}{C[\inr(b)/z]}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
In $\ind{A+B}$, $z$ is bound in $C$, $x$ is bound in $c$, and $y$ is bound in | |
$d$. | |
\subsection{The empty type \texorpdfstring{$\emptyt$}{0}} | |
\index{type!empty|(}% | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\emptyt$-\rform] | |
{\wfctx\Gamma} | |
{\oftp\Gamma\emptyt{\UU_i}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\emptyt$-\relim] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x\emptyt}{C}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{\emptyt}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{\emptyt}(x.C,a)}{C[a/x]}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
In $\ind{\emptyt}$, $x$ is bound in $C$. The empty type has no introduction rule and no computation rule. | |
\index{type!empty|)}% | |
\subsection{The unit type \texorpdfstring{$\unit$}{1}} | |
\label{sec:more-formal-unit} | |
\index{type!unit|(}% | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\rform] | |
{\wfctx\Gamma} | |
{\oftp\Gamma\unit{\UU_i}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\rintro] | |
{\wfctx\Gamma} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\ttt}{\unit}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\relim] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x\unit}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma}{c}{C[\ttt/x]} \\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{a}{\unit}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{\unit}(x.C,c,a)}{C[a/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\rcomp] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x\unit}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma}{c}{C[\ttt/x]}} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{\unit}(x.C,c,\ttt)}{c}{C[\ttt/x]}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
In $\ind{\unit}$ the variable $x$ is bound in $C$. | |
Notice that we do not postulate a judgmental uniqueness principle for the unit | |
type; see \cref{sec:finite-product-types} for a proof of the corresponding | |
propositional uniqueness statement. | |
\index{type!unit|)}% | |
\subsection{The natural number type} | |
\index{natural numbers|(}% | |
We give the rules for natural numbers, following \cref{sec:inductive-types}. | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\def\premise{ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x{\N}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{c_0}{C[0/x]} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp{x}\N,\tmtp y C}{c_s}{C[\suc(x)/x]}} | |
% | |
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\rform] | |
{\wfctx\Gamma} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\N}{\UU_i}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\rintro${}_1$] | |
{\wfctx\Gamma} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{0}{\N}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\rintro${}_2$] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{n}{\N}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\suc(n)}{\N}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\relim] | |
{\premise \\ \oftp\Gamma{n}{\N}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{\N}(x.C,c_0,x.y.c_s,n)}{C[n/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\rcomp${}_1$] | |
{\premise} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{\N}(x.C,c_0,x.y.c_s,0)}{c_0}{C[0/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\rcomp${}_2$] | |
{\premise \\ \oftp\Gamma{n}{\N}} | |
{\Gamma\vdash | |
{\begin{aligned}[t] | |
&\ind{\N}(x.C,c_0,x.y.c_s,\suc(n)) \\ | |
&\quad \jdeq c_s[n,\ind{\N}(x.C,c_0,x.y.c_s,n)/x,y] : C[\suc(n)/x] | |
\end{aligned}}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
In $\ind{\N}$, $x$ is bound in $C$, and $x$ and $y$ are bound in $c_s$. | |
Other inductively defined types follow the same general scheme. | |
\index{natural numbers|)}% | |
\subsection{Identity types} | |
\label{sec:more-formal-identity} | |
\index{type!identity|(}% | |
The presentation here corresponds to the (unbased) path induction principle for identity types in | |
\cref{sec:identity-types}. | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\idsym$-\rform] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{b}{A}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\id[A]{a}{b}}{\UU_i}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\idsym$-\rintro] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\refl a}{\id[A]aa}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\idsym$-\relim] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\tmtp yA,\tmtp p{\id[A]xy}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp zA}{c}{C[z,z,\refl z/x,y,p]} \\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{b}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{p'}{\id[A]ab}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\indid{A}(x.y.p.C,z.c,a,b,p')}{C[a,b,p'/x,y,p]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\idsym$-\rcomp] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\tmtp yA,\tmtp p{\id[A]xy}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp zA}{c}{C[z,z,\refl z/x,y,p]} \\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\indid{A}(x.y.p.C,z.c,a,a,\refl a)}{c[a/z]}{C[a,a,\refl a/x,y,p]}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
In $\indid{A}$, $x$, $y$, and $p$ are bound in $C$, and $z$ is bound in | |
$c$. | |
\index{type!identity|)}% | |
\subsection{Definitions} | |
\index{definition}% | |
Although the rules we have listed so far allow us to construct everything we need directly, we | |
would still like to be able to use named constants, such as $\isequiv$, as a matter of | |
convenience. Informally, we can think of these constants simply as | |
abbreviations, but the situation is a bit subtler in the formalization. | |
For example, consider function composition, which takes $f:A\to B$ and | |
$g:B\to C$ to $g\circ f:A\to C$. Somewhat unexpectedly, to make this work formally, $\circ$ must take as arguments not only $f$ and $g$, but also their types $A$, $B$, $C$: | |
% | |
\begin{narrowmultline*} | |
{\circ} \defeq \lam{A:\UU_i}{B:\UU_i}{C:\UU_i} | |
\narrowbreak | |
\lam{g:B\to C}{f:A\to B}{x:A} g(f(x)). | |
\end{narrowmultline*} | |
% | |
From a practical perspective, we do not want to annotate each application of | |
$\circ$ with $A$, $B$ and $C$, as they are usually quite easily guessed from surrounding information. We would like to simply write $g\circ f$. | |
Then, strictly speaking, $g \circ f$ is not an abbreviation for $\lam{x : A} g(f(x))$, | |
because it involves additional \define{implicit arguments} which we want to suppress. | |
\index{implicit argument} | |
Inference of implicit arguments, typical ambiguity\index{typical ambiguity} (\cref{sec:universes}), | |
ensuring that symbols are only defined once, etc., are collectively called | |
\define{elaboration}. \index{elaboration, in type theory} | |
Elaboration must take place prior to checking a derivation, and is | |
thus not usually presented as part of the core type theory. However, it is | |
essentially impossible to use any implementation of type theory which does not | |
perform elaboration; see \cite{Coq,norell2007towards} for further discussion. | |
\section{Homotopy type theory} | |
\label{sec:hott-features} | |
In this section we state the additional axioms of homotopy type theory which distinguish it from standard Martin-L\"{o}f type theory: function extensionality, the | |
univalence axiom, and higher inductive types. We state them in the style | |
of the second presentation \cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}, although the first presentation \cref{sec:syntax-informally} could be used just as well. | |
\subsection{Function extensionality and univalence} | |
There are two basic ways of introducing axioms which do not introduce new syntax or judgmental equalities (function extensionality and univalence are of this form): | |
either add a primitive constant to inhabit the axiom, or prove all theorems which depend on the axiom by hypothesizing a variable that inhabits the axiom, cf.\ \cref{sec:axioms}. | |
While these are essentially equivalent, we opt for the former approach because we feel that the axioms of homotopy type theory are an essential part of the core theory. | |
\index{function extensionality}% | |
\cref{axiom:funext} is formalized by introduction of a constant $\funext$ which | |
asserts that $\happly$ is an equivalence: | |
% | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\textsc{ext}] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{f}{\tprd{x:A} B} \\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{g}{\tprd{x:A} B}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\funext(f,g)}{\isequiv(\happly_{f,g})}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
The definitions of $\happly$ and $\isequiv$ can be found in~\eqref{eq:happly} and | |
\cref{sec:concluding-remarks}, respectively. | |
\index{univalence axiom}% | |
\cref{axiom:univalence} is formalized in a similar fashion, too: | |
% | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\UU_i$-\textsc{univ}] | |
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{B}{\UU_i}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\univalence(A,B)}{\isequiv(\idtoeqv_{A,B})}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
The definition of $\idtoeqv$ can be found in~\eqref{eq:uidtoeqv}. | |
\subsection{The circle} | |
\index{type!circle}% | |
Here we give an example of a basic higher inductive type; others follow the same | |
general scheme, albeit with elaborations. | |
Note that the rules below do not precisely follow the pattern of the ordinary | |
inductive types in \cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}: the rules refer to the | |
notions of transport and functoriality of maps (\cref{sec:functors}), and the | |
second computation rule is a propositional, not judgmental, equality. These | |
differences are discussed in \cref{sec:dependent-paths}. | |
\begin{mathparpagebreakable} | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sn^1$-\rform] | |
{\wfctx\Gamma} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\Sn^1}{\UU_i}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sn^1$-\rintro${}_1$] | |
{\wfctx\Gamma} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\base}{\Sn^1}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sn^1$-\rintro${}_2$] | |
{\wfctx\Gamma} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\lloop}{\id[\Sn^1]{\base}{\base}}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sn^1$-\relim] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x{\Sn^1}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma}{b}{C[\base/x]} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma}{\ell}{\dpath C \lloop b b} \\ | |
\oftp\Gamma{p}{\Sn^1}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{\Sn^1}(x.C,b,\ell,p)}{C[p/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sn^1$-\rcomp${}_1$] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x{\Sn^1}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma}{b}{C[\base/x]} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma}{\ell}{\dpath C \lloop b b}} | |
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{\Sn^1}(x.C,b,\ell,\base)}{b}{C[\base/x]}} | |
\and | |
\inferrule*[right=$\Sn^1$-\rcomp${}_2$] | |
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x{\Sn^1}}{C}{\UU_i} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma}{b}{C[\base/x]} \\ | |
\oftp{\Gamma}{\ell}{\dpath C \lloop b b}} | |
{\oftp\Gamma{\Sn^1\text{-}\mathsf{loopcomp}} | |
{\id {\apd{(\lamu{y:\Sn^1} \ind{\Sn^1}(x.C,b,\ell,y))}{\lloop}} {\ell}}} | |
\end{mathparpagebreakable} | |
% | |
In $\ind{\Sn^1}$, $x$ is bound in $C$. The notation ${\dpath C \lloop b b}$ for dependent paths was introduced in \cref{sec:dependent-paths}. | |
\index{rules of type theory|)}% | |
\section{Basic metatheory} | |
\index{metatheory|(}% | |
This section discusses the meta-theoretic properties of the type theory presented in | |
\cref{sec:syntax-informally}, and similar results hold for \cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}. Figuring out which of these still hold when we add the features from \cref{sec:hott-features} quickly leads to open questions,\index{open!problem} as discussed at the end of this section. | |
Recall that \cref{sec:syntax-informally} defines the terms of type theory as | |
an extension of the untyped $\lambda$-calculus. The $\lambda$-calculus | |
has its own notion of computation, namely the computation rule\index{computation rule!for function types}: | |
\[ | |
(\lam{x} t)(u) \defeq t[u/x]. | |
\] | |
This rule, together with the defining equations for the defined constants form | |
\emph{rewriting rules}\index{rewriting rule}\index{rule!rewriting} that determine reduction steps for a rewriting | |
system. These steps yield a notion of computation in the sense that each rule | |
has a natural direction: one simplifies $(\lam{x} t)(u)$ by evaluating the | |
function at its argument. | |
Moreover, this system is \emph{confluent}\index{confluence}, that is, if $a$ simplifies in some | |
number of steps to both $a'$ and $a''$, there is some $b$ to which both $a'$ and | |
$a''$ eventually simplify. Thus we can define $t\conv u$ to mean that $t$ and | |
$u$ simplify to the same term. | |
(The situation is similar in \cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}: Although there | |
we presented the computation rules as undirected equalities $\jdeq$, we can give | |
an operational semantics by saying that the application of an eliminator to an | |
introductory form simplifies to its equal, not the other way around.) | |
Using standard techniques from type theory, it is possible to show that the system in \cref{sec:syntax-informally} | |
has the following properties: | |
\begin{thm}\label{thm:conversion-preserves-typing} | |
If $A : \UU$ and $A \conv A'$ then $A' : \UU$. | |
If $t:A$ and $t \conv t'$ then $t':A$. | |
\end{thm} | |
We say that a term is \define{normalizable} | |
\indexdef{term!normalizable}% | |
\index{normalization}% | |
\indexdef{normalizable term}% | |
(respectively, \define{strongly | |
normalizable}) | |
\indexdef{term!strongly normalizable}% | |
\index{normalization!strong}% | |
\index{strong!normalization}% | |
if some (respectively, every), sequence of rewriting steps from the term | |
terminates. | |
\begin{thm}\label{thm:strong-normalization} | |
If $A : \UU$ then $A$ is strongly normalizable. | |
If $t:A$ then $A$ and $t$ are strongly normalizable. | |
\end{thm} | |
We say that a term is in \define{normal form} | |
\index{normal form}% | |
\index{term!normal form of}% | |
if it cannot be further | |
simplified, and that a term is \define{closed} | |
\index{closed!term}% | |
\index{term!closed}% | |
if no variable occurs freely in | |
it. A closed normal type has to be a primitive type, i.e., of the form | |
$c(\vec{v})$ for some primitive constant $c$ (where the list $\vec{v}$ of closed | |
normal terms may be omitted if empty, for instance, as with $\N$). In fact, we | |
can explicitly describe all normal forms: | |
\begin{lem}\label{lem:normal-forms} | |
The terms in normal form can be described by the following syntax: | |
% | |
\begin{align*} | |
v & \production k \mid \lam{x} v \mid c(\vec{v}) \mid f(\vec{v}), \\ | |
k &\production x \mid k(v) \mid f(\vec{v})(k), | |
\end{align*} | |
% | |
where $f(\vec{v})$ represents a partial application of the defined function $f$. | |
In particular, a type in normal form is of the form $k$ or $c(\vec{v})$. | |
\end{lem} | |
\begin{thm} | |
If $A$ is in normal form then the | |
judgment $A : \UU$ is decidable. If $A : \UU$ and $t$ is in normal form then the judgment | |
$t:A$ is decidable. | |
\end{thm} | |
Logical consistency\index{consistency} (of the system in \cref{sec:syntax-informally}) follows | |
immediately: if we had $a:\emptyt$ in the empty context, then by | |
\cref{thm:conversion-preserves-typing,thm:strong-normalization}, $a$ | |
simplifies to a normal term $a':\emptyt$. But by | |
\cref{lem:normal-forms} no such term exists. | |
\begin{cor} | |
The system in \cref{sec:syntax-informally} is logically consistent. | |
\end{cor} | |
Similarly, we have the \emph{canonicity}\indexdef{canonicity} property that if $a:\N$ in the empty | |
context, then $a$ simplifies to a normal term $\suc^k(0)$ for some numeral $k$. | |
\begin{cor} | |
The system in \cref{sec:syntax-informally} has the canonicity property. | |
\end{cor} | |
Finally, if $a,A$ are in normal form, it is \emph{decidable} whether $a:A$; in | |
other words, because type-checking amounts to verifying the correctness of a | |
proof, this means we can always ``recognize a correct proof when we see one''. | |
\begin{cor} | |
The property of being a proof in the system in \cref{sec:syntax-informally} is decidable. | |
\end{cor} | |
\mentalpause | |
The above results do not apply to the extended system of homotopy type | |
theory (i.e., the above system extended by \cref{sec:hott-features}), since | |
occurrences of the univalence axiom and constructors of higher inductive types | |
never simplify, breaking \cref{lem:normal-forms}. It is an open question\index{open!problem} | |
whether one can simplify applications of these constants in order to restore | |
canonicity. We also do not have a schema describing all permissible higher | |
inductive types, nor are we certain how to correctly formulate their rules | |
(e.g., whether the computation rules on higher constructors should be judgmental | |
equalities). | |
The consistency\index{consistency} of Martin-L\"{o}f type theory extended with univalence and higher | |
inductive types could be shown by inventing an appropriate normalization procedure, but currently | |
the only proofs that these systems are consistent are via semantic models---for | |
univalence, a model in Kan\index{Kan complex} complexes due to Voevodsky \cite{klv:ssetmodel}, and | |
for higher inductive types, a model due to Lumsdaine and Shulman \cite{ls:hits}. | |
Other metatheoretic issues, and a summary of our current results, are discussed | |
in greater length in the ``Constructivity'' and ``Open problems'' sections of | |
the introduction to this book. | |
\index{metatheory|)}% | |
\sectionNotes\label{subsec:general-remarks} | |
% This presentation is strongly inspired by two Martin-L\"of 1972 and 1973. | |
The system of rules with introduction (primitive constants) and elimination | |
and computation rules (defined constant) is inspired by Gentzen natural | |
deduction. The possibility of strengthening the elimination rule for | |
existential quantification was indicated in \cite{howard:pat}. The | |
strengthening of the axioms for disjunction appears in \cite{Martin-Lof-1972}, | |
and for absurdity elimination and identity type in \cite{Martin-Lof-1973}. The | |
$W$-types were introduced in \cite{Martin-Lof-1979}. They generalize a notion | |
of trees introduced by \cite{Tait-1968}. | |
\index{Martin-L\"of}% | |
%inspired from unpublished work of Spector. | |
The generalized form of primitive recursion for natural numbers and ordinals | |
appear in \cite{Hilbert-1925}. This motivated G\"odel's system $T$, | |
\cite{Goedel-T-1958}, which was analyzed by \cite{Tait-1966}, who used, | |
following \cite{Goedel-T-1958}, the terminology ``definitional equality'' for | |
conversion: two terms are \emph{judgmentally equal} if they reduce to a | |
common term by means of a sequence of applications of the reduction | |
rules. This terminology was also used by de Bruijn \cite{deBruijn-1973} in his | |
presentation of \emph{AUTOMATH}.\index{AUTOMATH} | |
Our second presentation comprises fairly standard presentation of | |
intensional Martin-L\"{o}f type theory, with some additional features needed in | |
homotopy type theory. Compared to a reference presentation of | |
\cite{hofmann:syntax-and-semantics}, the type theory of this book has a few | |
non-critical differences: | |
% | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item universes \`{a} la Russell, in the sense of | |
\cite{martin-lof:bibliopolis}; and | |
\item judgmental $\eta$ and function extensionality for $\Pi$ types; | |
\end{itemize} | |
and a few features essential for homotopy type theory: | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\item the univalence axiom; and | |
\item higher inductive types. | |
\end{itemize} | |
% | |
As a matter of convenience, the book primarily defines functions by induction | |
using definition by \emph{pattern matching}. | |
\index{pattern matching}% | |
\index{definition!by pattern matching}% | |
It is possible to formalize the | |
notion of pattern matching, as done in \cref{sec:syntax-informally}. However, the | |
standard type-theoretic presentation, adopted in \cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}, is to introduce a single \emph{dependent | |
eliminator} for each type former, from which functions out of that type must be | |
defined. This approach is easier to formalize both syntactically and | |
semantically, as it amounts to the universal property of the type former. | |
The two approaches are equivalent; see \cref{sec:pattern-matching} for a | |
longer discussion. | |
\index{type theory!formal|)}% | |
\index{formal!type theory|)}% | |
%%% Local Variables: | |
%%% mode: latex | |
%%% TeX-master: "hott-online" | |
%%% End: | |