Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
\chapter{Abelian categories} | |
In this chapter I'll translate some more familiar concepts into categorical language; | |
this will require some additional assumptions about our category, | |
culminating in the definition of a so-called ``abelian category''. | |
Once that's done, I'll be able to tell you what this ``diagram chasing'' thing is all about. | |
Throughout this chapter, ``$\injto$'' will be used for monic maps and ``$\surjto$'' for epic maps. | |
\section{Zero objects, kernels, cokernels, and images} | |
\prototype{In $\catname{Grp}$, the trivial group and homomorphism | |
are the zero objects and morphisms. | |
If $G$, $H$ are abelian then the cokernel | |
of $\phi : G \to H$ is $H/\img \phi$.} | |
A \vocab{zero object} of a category is an object $0$ which is both initial and terminal; | |
of course, it's unique up to unique isomorphism. | |
For example, in $\catname{Grp}$ the zero object is the trivial group, | |
in $\catname{Vect}_k$ it's the zero-dimensional vector space consisting of one point, and so on. | |
\begin{ques} | |
Show that $\catname{Set}$ and $\catname{Top}$ don't have zero objects. | |
\end{ques} | |
For the rest of this chapter, all categories will have zero objects. | |
In a category $\AA$ with zero objects, any two objects $A$ and $B$ thus have a distinguished morphism | |
\[ A \to 0 \to B \] | |
which is called the \vocab{zero morphism} and also denoted $0$. | |
For example, in $\catname{Grp}$ this is the trivial homomorphism. | |
We can now define: | |
\begin{definition} | |
Consider a map $A \taking f B$. | |
The \vocab{kernel} is defined as the equalizer of this map and the map $A \taking 0 B$. | |
Thus, it's a map $\ker f \colon \Ker f \injto A$ such that | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
\Ker f \ar[rd, "0", dashed] \ar[d, "\ker f"', hook] \\ | |
A \ar[r, "f"'] & B | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
commutes, and moreover any other map with the same property factors uniquely through $\Ker A$ | |
(so it is universal with this property). | |
By \Cref{prob:equalizer_monic}, $\ker f$ is a monic morphism, | |
which justifies the use of ``$\injto$''. | |
\end{definition} | |
Notice that we're using $\ker f$ to represent the map and $\Ker f$ to represent the object | |
Similarly, we define the cokernel, the dual notion: | |
\begin{definition} | |
Consider a map $A \taking f B$. | |
The \vocab{cokernel} of $f$ is a map $\coker f \colon B \surjto \Coker f$ such that | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
A \ar[r, "f"] \ar[rd, "0"', dashed] & B \ar[d, "\coker f", two heads] \\ | |
& \Coker f | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
commutes, and moreover any other map with the same property factors | |
uniquely through $\Coker f$ (so it is universal with this property). | |
Thus it is the ``coequalizer'' of this map and the map $A \taking 0 B$. | |
By the dual of \Cref{prob:equalizer_monic}, $\coker f$ is an epic morphism, | |
which justifies the use of ``$\surjto$''. | |
\end{definition} | |
Think of the cokernel of a map $A \taking f B$ as ``$B$ modulo the image of $f$''. | |
\begin{example} | |
[Cokernels] | |
Consider the map $\Zc6 \to D_{12} = \left\langle r,s \mid r^6=s^2=1, rs=sr\inv\right\rangle$. | |
Then the cokernel of this map in $\catname{Grp}$ is $D_{12} / \left\langle r \right\rangle \cong \Zc 2$. | |
\end{example} | |
This doesn't always work out quite the way we want since in general the image of | |
a homomorphism need not be normal in the codomain. | |
Nonetheless, we can use this to define: | |
\begin{definition} | |
The \vocab{image} of $A \taking f B$ is the kernel of $\coker f$. | |
We denote $\Img f = \Ker(\coker f)$. | |
This gives a unique map $\img f : A \to \Img f$. | |
\end{definition} | |
When it exists, this coincides with our concrete notion of ``image''. | |
Picture: | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
A \ar[rd, "\exists!"'] \ar[rr, "f"] \ar[rrrd, "0"', near start, dashed] | |
&& B \ar[rd, two heads, "\coker f"] \\ | |
& \Img f \ar[ur, hook] \ar[rr, "0", dashed] && \Coker f | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
Note that by universality of $\Img f$, | |
we find that there is a unique map | |
$\img f \colon A \to \Img f$ that makes the entire diagram commute. | |
\section{Additive and abelian categories} | |
\prototype{$\catname{Ab}$, $\catname{Vect}_k$, or more generally $\catname{Mod}_R$.} | |
We can now define the notion of an additive and abelian category, | |
which are the types of categories where this notion is most useful. | |
\begin{definition} | |
An \vocab{additive category} $\AA$ is one such that: | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\ii $\AA$ has a zero object, and any two objects have a product. | |
\ii More importantly: every $\Hom_\AA(A, B)$ forms an \emph{abelian group} (written additively) | |
such that composition distributes over addition: | |
\[ (g+h)\circ f = g\circ f + h\circ f | |
\quad\text{and}\quad | |
f\circ(g+h) = f\circ g + f \circ h. \] | |
The zero map serves as the identity element for each group. | |
\end{itemize} | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{definition} | |
An \vocab{abelian category} $\AA$ is one with the additional properties that | |
for any morphism $A \taking f B$, | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\ii The kernel and cokernel exist, and | |
\ii The morphism factors through the image so that $\img(f)$ is epic. | |
\end{itemize} | |
So, this yields a diagram | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
\Ker(f) \ar[rd, hook, "\ker(f)"'] | |
&& | |
\Img(f) \ar[rd, hook] | |
&& | |
\Coker(f) \\ | |
& A \ar[ru, "\img(f)", two heads] \ar[rr, "f"', dashed] | |
&& B \ar[ru, "\coker(f)"', two heads] | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{example}[Examples of abelian categories] | |
\listhack | |
\begin{enumerate}[(a)] | |
\ii $\catname{Vect}_k$, $\catname{Ab}$ are abelian categories, | |
where $f+g$ takes its usual meaning. | |
\ii Generalizing this, the category $\catname{Mod}_R$ of $R$-modules is abelian. | |
\ii $\catname{Grp}$ is not even additive, because there is no way to assign | |
a commutative addition to pairs of morphisms. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{example} | |
In general, once you assume a category is abelian, all the properties you would want | |
of these kernels, cokernels, \dots\ that you would guess hold true. | |
For example, | |
\begin{proposition}[Monic $\iff$ trival kernel] | |
A map $A \taking f B$ is monic if and only if its kernel is $0 \to A$. | |
Dually, $A \taking f B$ is epic if and only if its cokernel is $B \to 0$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
The easy direction is: | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Show that if $A \taking f B$ is monic, then $0 \to A$ is a kernel. | |
(This holds even in non-abelian categories.) | |
\end{exercise} | |
Of course, since kernels are unique up to isomorphism, monic $\implies$ $0$ kernel. | |
On the other hand, assume that $0 \to A$ is a kernel of $A \taking f B$. | |
For this we can exploit the group structure of the underlying homomorphisms now. | |
Assume the diagram | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
Z \ar[r, "g", shift left] \ar[r, "h"', shift right] & A \ar[r, "f"] & B | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
commutes. | |
Then $(g - h) \circ f = g \circ f - h \circ f = 0$, and we've arrived at a commutative diagram. | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
Z \ar[d, "g-h"'] \ar[rd, dashed, "0"] & \\ | |
A \ar[r, "f"'] & B | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
But since $0 \to A$ is a kernel it follows that $g-h$ factors through $0$, | |
so $g-h = 0 \implies g = h$, which is to say that $f$ is monic. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{proposition}[Isomorphism $\iff$ monic and epic] | |
In an abelian category, | |
a map is an isomorphism if and only if it is monic and epic. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Omitted. (The Mitchell embedding theorem | |
presented later implies this anyways for | |
most situations we care about, | |
by looking at a small sub-category.) | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{Exact sequences} | |
\prototype{$0 \to G \to G \times H \to H \to 0$ is exact.} | |
Exact sequences will seem exceedingly unmotivated until you learn about homology groups, | |
which is one of the most natural places that exact sequences appear. | |
In light of this, it might be worth trying to read the chapter on homology groups | |
simultaneously with this one. | |
First, let me state the definition for groups, to motivate the general categorical definition. | |
A sequence of groups | |
\[ G_0 \taking{f_1} G_1 \taking{f_2} G_2 \taking{f_3} \dots \taking{f_n} G_n \] | |
is \emph{exact} at $G_k$ if the image of $f_k$ is the kernel of $f_{k+1}$. | |
We say the entire sequence is exact if it's exact at $k=1,\dots,n-1$. | |
\begin{example} | |
[Exact sequences] | |
\listhack | |
\begin{enumerate}[(a)] | |
\ii The sequence | |
\[ 0 \to \Zc 3 | |
\overset{\times 5}{\injto} \Zc{15} | |
\surjto \Zc{5} | |
\to 0 \] | |
is exact. | |
Actually, $0 \to G \injto G \times H \surjto H \to 0$ is exact in general. | |
(Here $0$ denotes the trivial group.) | |
\ii For groups, the map $0 \to A \to B$ is exact if and only if $A \to B$ is injective. | |
\ii For groups, the map $A \to B \to 0$ is exact if and only if $A \to B$ is surjective. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{example} | |
Now, we want to mimic this definition in a general \emph{abelian} category $\AA$. | |
So, let's write down a criterion for when $A \taking f B \taking g C$ is exact. | |
First, we had better have that $g \circ f = 0$, | |
which encodes the fact that $\img(f) \subseteq \ker(g)$. | |
Adding in all the relevant objects, we get the commutative diagram below. | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
A \ar[rd, "f"] \ar[rr, dashed, "0"] \ar[dd, "\img f"', two heads] && C \\ | |
& B \ar[ru, "g"] \\ | |
\Img f \ar[ru, hook, "\iota"] \ar[rr, dashed, "\exists!"] && | |
\Ker g \ar["0"', dashed, uu] \ar[lu, hook'] | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
Here the map $A \surjto \Img f$ is epic since we are assuming $\AA$ is an abelian category. | |
So, we have that | |
\[ 0 = (g \circ \iota) \circ \img f = g \circ (\iota \circ \img f) = g \circ f = 0 \] | |
but since $\img f$ is epic, this means that $g \circ \iota = 0$. | |
So there is a \emph{unique} map $\Img f \to \Ker g$, and we require that this diagram commutes. | |
In short, | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $\AA$ be an abelian category. The sequence | |
\[ \dots \to A_{n-1} \taking{f_n} A_n \taking{f_{n+1}} A_{n+1} \to \dots \] | |
is \vocab{exact} at $A_n$ if $f_n \circ f_{n+1} = 0$ and | |
the canonical map $\Img f_n \to \Ker f_{n+1}$ is an isomorphism. | |
The entire sequence is exact if it is exact at each $A_i$. | |
(For finite sequences we don't impose condition on the very first and very last object.) | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Show that, as before, $0 \to A \to B$ is exact $\iff$ $A \to B$ is monic. | |
\end{exercise} | |
\section{The Freyd-Mitchell embedding theorem} | |
We now introduce the Freyd-Mitchell embedding theorem, | |
which essentially says that any abelian category can be realized as a concrete one. | |
\begin{definition} | |
A category is \vocab{small} if $\obj(\AA)$ is a set (as opposed to a class), | |
i.e.\ there is a ``set of all objects in $\AA$''. | |
For example, $\catname{Set}$ is not small because there is no set of all sets. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{theorem} | |
[Freyd-Mitchell embedding theorem] | |
Let $\AA$ be a small abelian category. | |
Then there exists a ring $R$ (with $1$ but possibly non-commutative) | |
and a full, faithful, exact functor onto the category of left $R$-modules. | |
\end{theorem} | |
Here a functor is \vocab{exact} if it preserves exact sequences. | |
This theorem is good because it means | |
\begin{moral} | |
You can basically forget about all the weird definitions | |
that work in any abelian category. | |
\end{moral} | |
Any time you're faced with a statement about an abelian category, | |
it suffices to just prove it for a ``concrete'' category | |
where injective/surjective/kernel/image/exact/etc.\ | |
agree with your previous notions. | |
A proof by this means is sometimes called \emph{diagram chasing}. | |
\begin{remark} | |
The ``small'' condition is a technical obstruction | |
that requires the objects $\AA$ to actually form a set. | |
I'll ignore this distinction, | |
because one can almost always work around it | |
by doing enough set-theoretic technicalities. | |
\end{remark} | |
For example, let's prove: | |
\begin{lemma} | |
[Short five lemma] | |
In an abelian category, consider the commutative diagram | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
0 \ar[r] | |
& A \ar[r, hook, "p"] \ar[d, "\alpha", "\cong"'] | |
& B \ar[r, two heads, "q"] \ar[d, "\beta"] | |
& C \ar[r] \ar[d, "\gamma", "\cong"'] | |
& 0 \\ | |
0 \ar[r] & A' \ar[r, hook, "p'"'] & B' \ar[r, two heads, "q'"'] & C' \ar[r] & 0 | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
and assume the top and bottom rows are exact. | |
If $\alpha$ and $\gamma$ are isomorphisms, then so is $\beta$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We prove that $\beta$ is epic (with a similar proof to get monic). | |
% One can show that it's possible to take a small subcategory of $\AA$ | |
% containing the $10$ elements and $13$ arrows above, as well as all necessary | |
% kernels, cokernels, et cetera. | |
% (Essentially, let $\BB_0$ be the diagram above and let $\BB_{i+1}$ add in any needed objects; | |
% then $\bigcup \BB_i$ is a set-sized category). | |
By the embedding theorem we can treat the category as $R$-modules over some $R$. | |
This lets us do a so-called ``diagram chase'' where we move elements around the picture, | |
using the concrete interpretation of our category as $R$-modules. | |
Let $b'$ be an element of $B'$. | |
Then $q'(b') \in C'$, and since $\gamma$ is surjective, we have a $c$ such that $\gamma(c) = b'$, | |
and finally a $b \in B$ such that $q(b) = c$. | |
Picture: | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
b \in B \ar[r, "q", mapsto] \ar[d, "\beta"', dashed] & c \in C \ar[d, "\gamma", "\cong"', mapsto] \\ | |
b' \in B' \ar[r, mapsto, "q'"] & c' \in C' | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
Now, it is not necessarily the case that $\beta(b) = b'$. | |
However, since the diagram commutes we at least have that | |
\[ q'(b') = q'(\beta(b)) \] | |
so $b' - \beta(b) \in \Ker q' = \Img p'$, and there is an $a' \in A'$ such that | |
$p'(a') = b' - \beta(b)$; | |
use $\alpha$ now to lift it to $a \in A$. | |
Picture: | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
a \in A \ar[d, mapsto] & b \in B \\ | |
a' \in A' \ar[r, mapsto] & b' - \beta(b) \in B' \ar[r, mapsto] & 0 \in C | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
Then, we have | |
\[ | |
\beta(b + q(a)) = \beta b + \beta p a | |
= \beta b + p' \alpha a | |
= \beta b + (b' - \beta b) | |
= b' | |
\] | |
so $b' \in \Img \beta$ which completes the proof that $\beta'$ is surjective. | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{Breaking long exact sequences} | |
\prototype{First isomorphism theorem.} | |
In fact, it turns out that any exact sequence breaks into short exact sequences. | |
This relies on: | |
\begin{proposition}[``First isomorphism theorem'' in abelian categories] | |
\label{prop:break_exact} | |
Let $A \taking f B$ be an arrow of an abelian category. | |
Then there is an exact sequence | |
\[ 0 \to \Ker f \taking{\ker f} A \taking{\img f} \Img f \to 0. \] | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{example} | |
Let's analyze this theorem in our two examples of abelian categories: | |
\begin{enumerate}[(a)] | |
\ii In the category of abelian groups, | |
this is basically the first isomorphism theorem. | |
\ii In the category $\catname{Vect}_k$, | |
this amounts to the rank-nullity theorem, \Cref{thm:rank_nullity}. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{example} | |
Thus, any exact sequence can be broken into short exact sequences, as | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd}[sep=0.8em] | |
&& 0 \ar[rd] && 0 && 0 \ar[rd] && 0 \\ | |
&&& C_{n} \ar[rd] \ar[ru] &&&& C_{n+2} \ar[ru] \ar[rd] \\ | |
{\color{red}\dots} \ar[rr, red] \ar[rd] | |
&& {\color{red}A_{n-1}} \ar[rr, "f_{n-1}"', red] \ar[ru] | |
&& {\color{red}A_n} \ar[rr, "f_n", red] \ar[rd] | |
&& {\color{red}A_{n+1}} \ar[rr, "f_{n+1}"', red] \ar[ru] | |
&& \dots | |
\\ | |
& C_{n-1} \ar[ru] \ar[rd] &&&& C_{n+1} \ar[ru] \ar[rd] \\ | |
0 \ar[ru] && 0 && 0 \ar[ru] && 0 | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
where $C_k = \img f_{k-1} = \ker f_k$ for every $k$. | |
\section\problemhead | |
\begin{problem} | |
[Four lemma] | |
In an abelian category, consider the commutative diagram | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
A \ar[r, "p"] \ar[d, "\alpha"', two heads] | |
& B \ar[r, "q"] \ar[d, "\beta"', hook] | |
& C \ar[r, "r"] \ar[d, "\gamma"'] | |
& D \ar[d, "\delta"', hook] \\ | |
A' \ar[r, "p'"'] & B' \ar[r, "q'"'] & C' \ar[r, "r'"'] & D' | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
where the first and second rows are exact. | |
Prove that if $\alpha$ is epic, and $\beta$ and $\delta$ are monic, | |
then $\gamma$ is monic. | |
\begin{sol} | |
Let $c \in C$ with $\gamma(c) = 0$. | |
We show $c = 0$. | |
This proceeds in a diagram chase: | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\ii Note that $0 = r'(\gamma(c)) = \delta(r(c))$, and since $\delta$ | |
is injective, it follows that $r(c) = 0$. | |
\ii Since the top row is exact, | |
it follows $c = q(b)$ for some $b \in B$. | |
\ii Then $q'(\beta(b)) = 0$, | |
so if we let $b' = \beta(b)$, | |
then $b' \in \ker(q')$. | |
As the bottom row is exact, there exists $a'$ with $p'(a') = b'$. | |
\ii Since $\alpha$ is injective, | |
there is $a \in A$ with $\alpha(a) = a'$. | |
\ii Since $\beta$ is injective, | |
it follows that $p(a) = b$. | |
\ii Since the top row is exact, and $b$ is in the image of $p$, | |
it follows that $0 = q(b) = c$ as needed. | |
\end{itemize} | |
\end{sol} | |
\end{problem} | |
\begin{problem} | |
[Five lemma] | |
\gim | |
In an abelian category, consider the commutative diagram | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
A \ar[r, "p"] \ar[d, "\alpha"', two heads] | |
& B \ar[r, "q"] \ar[d, "\beta"', "\cong"] | |
& C \ar[r, "r"] \ar[d, "\gamma"'] | |
& D \ar[r, "s"] \ar[d, "\delta"', "\cong"] | |
& E \ar[d, "\eps"', hook] \\ | |
A' \ar[r, "p'"'] & B' \ar[r, "q'"'] & C' \ar[r, "r'"'] & D' \ar[r, "s'"'] & E' | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
where the two rows are exact, | |
$\beta$ and $\delta$ are isomorphisms, | |
$\alpha$ is epic, and $\eps$ is monic. | |
Prove that $\gamma$ is an isomorphism. | |
\end{problem} | |
\begin{sproblem} | |
[Snake lemma] | |
\gim | |
In an abelian category, consider the diagram | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
& A \ar[r, "f"] \ar[d, "a"] & B \ar[r, "g", two heads] \ar[d, "b"] & C \ar[r] \ar[d, "c"] & 0 \\ | |
0 \ar[r] & A' \ar[r, hook, "f'"'] & B' \ar[r, "g'"'] & C' | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
where the first and second rows are exact sequences. | |
Prove that there is an exact sequence | |
\[ \Ker a \to \Ker b \to \Ker c \to \Coker a \to \Coker b \to \Coker c. \] | |
\end{sproblem} | |