Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
\chapter{Cardinals} | |
An ordinal measures a total ordering. | |
However, it does not do a fantastic job at measuring size. | |
For example, there is a bijection between the elements of $\omega$ and $\omega+1$: | |
\[ | |
\begin{array}{rccccccc} | |
\omega+1 = & \{ & \omega & 0 & 1 & 2 & \dots & \} \\ | |
\omega = & \{ & 0 & 1 & 2 & 3 & \dots & \}. | |
\end{array} | |
\] | |
In fact, as you likely already know, | |
there is even a bijection between $\omega$ and $\omega^2$: | |
\[ | |
\begin{array}{l|cccccc} | |
+ & 0 & 1 & 2 & 3 & 4 & \dots \\ \hline | |
0 & 0 & 1 & 3 & 6 & 10 & \dots \\ | |
\omega & 2 & 4 & 7 & 11 & \dots & \\ | |
\omega \cdot 2 & 5 & 8 & 12 & \dots & & \\ | |
\omega \cdot 3 & 9 & 13 & \dots & & & \\ | |
\omega \cdot 4 & 14 & \dots & & & & | |
\end{array} | |
\] | |
So ordinals do not do a good job of keeping track of size. | |
For this, we turn to the notion of a cardinal number. | |
\section{Equinumerous sets and cardinals} | |
\begin{definition} | |
Two sets $A$ and $B$ are \vocab{equinumerous}, written $A \approx B$, | |
if there is a bijection between them. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{definition} | |
A \vocab{cardinal} is an ordinal $\kappa$ such that | |
for no $\alpha < \kappa$ do we have $\alpha \approx \kappa$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{example}[Examples of cardinals] | |
Every finite number is a cardinal. | |
Moreover, $\omega$ is a cardinal. | |
However, $\omega+1$, $\omega^2$, $\omega^{2015}$ are not, | |
because they are countable. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{example}[$\omega^\omega$ is countable] | |
Even $\omega^\omega$ is not a cardinal, | |
since it is a countable union | |
\[ \omega^\omega = \bigcup_n \omega^n \] | |
and each $\omega^n$ is countable. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{ques} | |
Why must an infinite cardinal be a limit ordinal? | |
\end{ques} | |
\begin{remark} | |
There is something fishy about the definition of a cardinal: | |
it relies on an \emph{external} function $f$. | |
That is, to verify $\kappa$ is a cardinal I can't just look at $\kappa$ itself; | |
I need to examine the entire universe $V$ to make sure | |
there does not exist a bijection $f : \kappa \to \alpha$ for $\alpha < \kappa$. | |
For now this is no issue, but later in model theory | |
this will lead to some highly counterintuitive behavior. | |
\end{remark} | |
\section{Cardinalities} | |
Now that we have defined a cardinal, we can discuss the size | |
of a set by linking it to a cardinal. | |
\begin{definition} | |
The \vocab{cardinality} of a set $X$ | |
is the \emph{least} ordinal $\kappa$ such that $X \approx \kappa$. | |
We denote it by $\left\lvert X \right\rvert$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{ques} | |
Why must $\left\lvert X \right\rvert$ be a cardinal? | |
\end{ques} | |
\begin{remark} | |
One needs the well-ordering theorem (equivalently, choice) | |
in order to establish that such an ordinal $\kappa$ actually exists. | |
\end{remark} | |
Since cardinals are ordinals, it makes sense to ask whether $\kappa_1 \le \kappa_2$, | |
and so on. | |
Our usual intuition works well here. | |
\begin{proposition}[Restatement of cardinality properties] | |
Let $X$ and $Y$ be sets. | |
\begin{enumerate}[(i)] | |
\ii $X \approx Y$ if and only $\left\lvert X \right\rvert = \left\lvert Y \right\rvert$, | |
if and only if there's a bijection from $X$ to $Y$. | |
\ii $\left\lvert X \right\rvert \le \left\lvert Y \right\rvert$ | |
if and only if there is an injective map $X \injto Y$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{proposition} | |
Diligent readers are invited to try and prove this. | |
\section{Aleph numbers} | |
\prototype{$\aleph_0 = \omega$, and $\aleph_1$ is the first uncountable ordinal.} | |
First, let us check that cardinals can get arbitrarily large: | |
\begin{proposition} | |
We have $\left\lvert X \right\rvert < \left\lvert \PP(X) \right\rvert$ for every set $X$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
There is an injective map $X \injto \PP(X)$ | |
but there is no injective map $\PP(X) \injto X$ by \Cref{lem:cantor_diag}. | |
\end{proof} | |
Thus we can define: | |
\begin{definition} | |
For a cardinal $\kappa$, we define $\kappa^+$ to be the least cardinal above $\kappa$, | |
called the \vocab{successor cardinal}. | |
\end{definition} | |
This $\kappa^+$ exists and has $\kappa^+ \le \left\lvert \PP(\kappa) \right\rvert$. | |
Next, we claim that: | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Show that if $A$ is a set of cardinals, then $\cup A$ is a cardinal. | |
\end{exercise} | |
Thus by transfinite induction we obtain that: | |
\begin{definition} | |
For any $\alpha \in \On$, we define the \vocab{aleph numbers} as | |
\begin{align*} | |
\aleph_0 &= \omega \\ | |
\aleph_{\alpha+1} &= \left( \aleph_\alpha \right)^+ \\ | |
\aleph_{\lambda} &= \bigcup_{\alpha < \lambda} \aleph_\alpha. | |
\end{align*} | |
\end{definition} | |
Thus we have the sequence of cardinals | |
\[ | |
0 < 1 < 2 < \dots < \aleph_0 < \aleph_1 < \dots < \aleph_\omega < \aleph_{\omega+1} < \dots. | |
\] | |
By definition, $\aleph_0$ is the cardinality of the natural numbers, | |
$\aleph_1$ is the first uncountable ordinal, \dots. | |
We claim the aleph numbers constitute all the cardinals: | |
\begin{lemma}[Aleph numbers constitute all infinite cardinals] | |
If $\kappa$ is a cardinal then | |
either $\kappa$ is finite (i.e.\ $\kappa \in \omega$) or | |
$\kappa = \aleph_\alpha$ for some $\alpha \in \On$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Assume $\kappa$ is infinite, and take $\alpha$ minimal with $\aleph_\alpha \ge \kappa$. | |
Suppose for contradiction that we have $\aleph_\alpha > \kappa$. | |
We may assume $\alpha > 0$, since the case $\alpha = 0$ is trivial. | |
If $\alpha = \ol\alpha + 1$ is a successor, then | |
\[ \aleph_{\ol\alpha} < \kappa < \aleph_{\alpha} | |
= (\aleph_{\ol\alpha})^+ \] | |
which contradicts the definition of the successor cardinal. | |
If $\alpha = \lambda$ is a limit ordinal, then $\aleph_\lambda$ is the | |
supremum $\bigcup_{\gamma < \lambda} \aleph_\gamma$. | |
So there must be some $\gamma < \lambda$ with $\aleph_\gamma > \kappa$, | |
which contradicts the minimality of $\alpha$. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{definition} | |
An infinite cardinal which is not a successor cardinal | |
is called a \vocab{limit cardinal}. | |
It is exactly those cardinals of the form $\aleph_\lambda$, | |
for $\lambda$ a limit ordinal, plus $\aleph_0$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\section{Cardinal arithmetic} | |
\prototype{$\aleph_0 \cdot \aleph_0 = \aleph_0 + \aleph_0 = \aleph_0$} | |
Recall the way we set up ordinal arithmetic. | |
Note that in particular, $\omega + \omega > \omega$ and $\omega^2 > \omega$. | |
Since cardinals count size, this property is undesirable, and | |
we want to have | |
\begin{align*} | |
\aleph_0 + \aleph_0 &= \aleph_0 \\ | |
\aleph_0 \cdot \aleph_0 &= \aleph_0 | |
\end{align*} | |
because $\omega + \omega$ and $\omega \cdot \omega$ are countable. | |
In the case of cardinals, we simply ``ignore order''. | |
The definition of cardinal arithmetic is as expected: | |
\begin{definition}[Cardinal arithmetic] | |
Given cardinals $\kappa$ and $\mu$, define | |
\[ \kappa + \mu | |
\defeq | |
\left\lvert | |
\left( \left\{ 0 \right\} \times \kappa \right) | |
\cup | |
\left( \left\{ 1 \right\} \times \mu \right) | |
\right\rvert | |
\] | |
and | |
\[ | |
\kappa \cdot \mu | |
\defeq | |
\left\lvert \mu \times \kappa \right\rvert | |
. | |
\] | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{ques} | |
Check this agrees with what you learned in pre-school | |
for finite cardinals. | |
\end{ques} | |
\begin{abuse} | |
This is a slight abuse of notation since we are using | |
the same symbols as for ordinal arithmetic, | |
even though the results are different ($\omega \cdot \omega = \omega^2$ | |
but $\aleph_0 \cdot \aleph_0 = \aleph_0$). | |
In general, I'll make it abundantly clear whether I am talking | |
about cardinal arithmetic or ordinal arithmetic. | |
\end{abuse} | |
To help combat this confusion, we use separate symbols for ordinals and cardinals. | |
Specifically, $\omega$ will always refer to $\{0,1,\dots\}$ viewed as an ordinal; | |
$\aleph_0$ will always refer to the same set viewed as a cardinal. | |
More generally, | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $\omega_\alpha = \aleph_\alpha$ viewed as an ordinal. | |
\end{definition} | |
However, as we've seen already we have that $\aleph_0 \cdot \aleph_0 = \aleph_0$. | |
In fact, this holds even more generally: | |
\begin{theorem}[Infinite cardinals squared] | |
Let $\kappa$ be an infinite cardinal. | |
Then $\kappa \cdot \kappa = \kappa$. | |
\end{theorem} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Obviously $\kappa \cdot \kappa \ge \kappa$, | |
so we want to show $\kappa \cdot \kappa \le \kappa$. | |
The idea is to try to repeat the same proof | |
that we had for $\aleph_0 \cdot \aleph_0 = \aleph_0$, | |
so we re-iterate it here. We took the ``square'' of | |
elements of $\aleph_0$, and then | |
\emph{re-ordered} it according to the diagonal: | |
\[ | |
\begin{array}{l|cccccc} | |
& 0 & 1 & 2 & 3 & 4 & \dots \\ \hline | |
0 & 0 & 1 & 3 & 6 & 10 & \dots \\ | |
1 & 2 & 4 & 7 & 11 & \dots & \\ | |
2 & 5 & 8 & 12 & \dots & & \\ | |
3 & 9 & 13 & \dots & & & \\ | |
4 & 14 & \dots & & & & | |
\end{array} | |
\] | |
We'd like to copy this idea for a general $\kappa$; | |
however, since addition is less well-behaved for infinite ordinals | |
it will be more convenient to use $\max\{\alpha,\beta\}$ | |
rather than $\alpha+\beta$. | |
Specifically, we put the ordering $<_{\text{max}}$ | |
on $\kappa \times \kappa$ as follows: | |
for $(\alpha_1, \beta_1)$ and $(\alpha_2, \beta_2)$ in $\kappa \times \kappa$ | |
we declare $(\alpha_1, \beta_1) <_{\text{max}} (\alpha_2, \beta_2)$ if | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\ii $\max \left\{ \alpha_1, \beta_1 \right\} < \max \left\{ \alpha_2, \beta_2 \right\}$ or | |
\ii $\max \left\{ \alpha_1, \beta_1 \right\} = \max \left\{ \alpha_2, \beta_2 \right\}$ and $(\alpha_1, \beta_1)$ | |
is lexicographically earlier than $(\alpha_2, \beta_2)$. | |
\end{itemize} | |
This alternate ordering (which deliberately avoids referring | |
to the addition) looks like: | |
\[ | |
\begin{array}{l|cccccc} | |
& 0 & 1 & 2 & 3 & 4 & \dots \\ \hline | |
0 & 0 & 1 & 4 & 9 & 16 & \dots \\ | |
1 & 2 & 3 & 5 & 10 & 17 & \dots \\ | |
2 & 6 & 7 & 8 & 11 & 18 & \dots \\ | |
3 & 12 & 13 & 14 & 15 & 19 & \dots \\ | |
4 & 20 & 21 & 22 & 23 & 24 & \dots \\ | |
\vdots & \vdots & \vdots & \vdots & \vdots & \vdots & \ddots \\ | |
\end{array} | |
\] | |
Now we proceed by transfinite induction on $\kappa$. | |
The base case is $\kappa = \aleph_0$, done above. | |
Now, $<_{\text{max}}$ is a well-ordering of $\kappa \times \kappa$, | |
so we know it is in order-preserving bijection with some ordinal $\gamma$. | |
Our goal is to show that $\left\lvert \gamma \right\rvert \le \kappa$. | |
To do so, it suffices to prove that for any $\ol\gamma \in \gamma$, | |
we have $\left\lvert \ol\gamma \right\rvert < \kappa$. | |
Suppose $\ol\gamma$ corresponds to the point $(\alpha, \beta) \in \kappa \times \kappa$ | |
under this bijection. | |
If $\alpha$ and $\beta$ are both finite | |
then certainly $\ol\gamma$ is finite too. | |
Otherwise, let $\ol\kappa = \max \{\alpha, \beta\} < \kappa$; | |
then the number of points below $\ol\gamma$ is at most | |
\[ | |
\left\lvert \alpha \right\rvert \cdot \left\lvert \beta \right\rvert | |
\le \ol\kappa \cdot \ol\kappa | |
= \ol\kappa | |
\] | |
by the inductive hypothesis. | |
So $\left\lvert \ol\gamma \right\rvert \le \ol\kappa < \kappa$ as desired. | |
\end{proof} | |
From this it follows that cardinal addition and multiplication is really boring: | |
\begin{theorem}[Infinite cardinal arithmetic is trivial] | |
Given cardinals $\kappa$ and $\mu$, | |
one of which is infinite, we have | |
\[ \kappa \cdot \mu = \kappa + \mu | |
= \max\left\{ \kappa, \mu \right\}.\] | |
\end{theorem} | |
\begin{proof} | |
The point is that both of these are less than the square of the maximum. | |
Writing out the details: | |
\begin{align*} | |
\max \left\{ \kappa, \mu \right\} | |
&\le \kappa + \mu \\ | |
&\le \kappa \cdot \mu \\ | |
&\le \max \left\{ \kappa, \mu \right\} | |
\cdot \max \left\{ \kappa, \mu \right\} \\ | |
&= \max\left\{ \kappa, \mu \right\}. \qedhere | |
\end{align*} | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{Cardinal exponentiation} | |
\prototype{$2^\kappa = \left\lvert \PP(\kappa) \right\rvert$.} | |
\begin{definition} | |
Suppose $\kappa$ and $\lambda$ are cardinals. | |
Then | |
\[ \kappa^\lambda | |
\defeq \left\lvert \mathscr F(\lambda, \kappa) \right\rvert. | |
\] | |
Here $\mathscr F(A,B)$ is the set of functions from $A$ to $B$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{abuse} | |
As before, we are using the same notation for | |
both cardinal and ordinal arithmetic. Sorry! | |
\end{abuse} | |
In particular, $2^\kappa = \left\lvert \PP(\kappa) \right\rvert > \kappa$, | |
and so from now on we can use the notation $2^\kappa$ freely. | |
(Note that this is totally different from ordinal arithmetic; | |
there we had $2^\omega = \bigcup_{n\in\omega} 2^n = \omega$. | |
In cardinal arithmetic $2^{\aleph_0} > \aleph_0$.) | |
I have unfortunately not told you what $2^{\aleph_0}$ equals. | |
A natural conjecture is that $2^{\aleph_0} = \aleph_1$; this is called the | |
\vocab{Continuum Hypothesis}. | |
It turns out that this is \emph{undecidable} -- it is not possible | |
to prove or disprove this from the $\ZFC$ axioms. | |
\section{Cofinality} | |
\prototype{$\aleph_0$, $\aleph_1$, \dots\ are all regular, but $\aleph_\omega$ has cofinality $\omega$.} | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $\lambda$ be an ordinal (usually a limit ordinal), | |
and $\alpha$ another ordinal. | |
A map $f : \alpha \to \lambda$ of ordinals is called \vocab{cofinal} | |
if for every $\ol\lambda < \lambda$, there is some $\ol\alpha \in \alpha$ | |
such that $f(\ol\alpha) \ge \ol\lambda$. | |
In other words, the map reaches arbitrarily high into $\lambda$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{example} | |
[Example of a cofinal map] | |
\listhack | |
\begin{enumerate}[(a)] | |
\ii The map $\omega \to \omega^\omega$ by $n \mapsto \omega^n$ is cofinal. | |
\ii For any ordinal $\alpha$, the identity map $\alpha \to \alpha$ is cofinal. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $\lambda$ be a limit ordinal. | |
The \vocab{cofinality} of $\lambda$, denoted $\cof(\lambda)$, | |
is the smallest ordinal $\alpha$ such that there is a cofinal map | |
$\alpha \to \lambda$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{ques} | |
Why must $\alpha$ be an infinite cardinal? | |
\end{ques} | |
Usually, we are interested in taking the cofinality of a cardinal $\kappa$. | |
Pictorially, you can imagine standing at the bottom of the universe and looking | |
up the chain of ordinals to $\kappa$. | |
You have a machine gun and are firing bullets upwards, and you want to get arbitrarily | |
high but less than $\kappa$. | |
The cofinality is then the number of bullets you need to do this. | |
We now observe that ``most'' of the time, the cofinality of a cardinal is itself. | |
Such a cardinal is called \vocab{regular}. | |
\begin{example}[$\aleph_0$ is regular] | |
$\cof(\aleph_0) = \aleph_0$, because no finite subset of | |
$\aleph_ 0 = \omega$ can reach arbitrarily high. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{example}[$\aleph_1$ is regular] | |
$\cof(\aleph_1) = \aleph_1$. | |
Indeed, assume for contradiction that some countable | |
set of ordinals $A = \{ \alpha_0, \alpha_1, \dots \} \subseteq \aleph_1$ | |
reaches arbitrarily high inside $\aleph_1$. | |
Then $\Lambda = \cup A$ is a \emph{countable} ordinal, | |
because it is a countable union of countable ordinals. | |
In other words $\Lambda \in \aleph_1$. | |
But $\Lambda$ is an upper bound for $A$, contradiction. | |
\end{example} | |
On the other hand, there \emph{are} cardinals which are not regular; | |
since these are the ``rare'' cases we call them \vocab{singular}. | |
\begin{example}[$\aleph_\omega$ is not regular] | |
Notice that $\aleph_0 < \aleph_1 < \aleph_2 < \dots$ reaches | |
arbitrarily high in $\aleph_\omega$, despite only having $\aleph_0$ terms. | |
It follows that $\cof(\aleph_\omega) = \aleph_0$. | |
\end{example} | |
We now confirm a suspicion you may have: | |
\begin{theorem} | |
[Successor cardinals are regular] | |
If $\kappa = \ol\kappa^+$ is a successor cardinal, | |
then it is regular. | |
\end{theorem} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We copy the proof that $\aleph_1$ was regular. | |
Assume for contradiction that for some $\mu \le \ol\kappa$, | |
there are $\mu$ sets reaching arbitrarily high in $\kappa$ as a cardinal. | |
Observe that each of these sets must have cardinality at most $\ol\kappa$. | |
We take the union of all $\mu$ sets, which gives an ordinal $\Lambda$ | |
serving as an upper bound. | |
The number of elements in the union is at most | |
\[ \#\text{sets} \cdot \#\text{elms} | |
\le \mu \cdot \ol\kappa = \ol\kappa \] | |
and hence $\left\lvert \Lambda \right\rvert \le \ol\kappa < \kappa$. | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{Inaccessible cardinals} | |
So, what about limit cardinals? | |
It seems to be that most of them are singular: if $\aleph_\lambda \ne \aleph_0$ is a limit ordinal, | |
then the sequence $\{\aleph_\alpha\}_{\alpha \in \lambda}$ (of length $\lambda$) is certainly cofinal. | |
\begin{example}[Beth fixed point] | |
Consider the monstrous cardinal | |
\[ \kappa = \aleph_{\aleph_{\aleph_{\ddots}}}. \] | |
This might look frighteningly huge, as $\kappa = \aleph_\kappa$, | |
but its cofinality is $\omega$ as it is the limit of the sequence | |
\[ \aleph_0, \aleph_{\aleph_0}, \aleph_{\aleph_{\aleph_0}}, \dots \] | |
\end{example} | |
More generally, one can in fact prove that | |
\[ \cof(\aleph_\lambda) = \cof(\lambda). \] | |
But it is actually conceivable that $\lambda$ is so large | |
that $\left\lvert \lambda \right\rvert = \left\lvert \aleph_\lambda \right\rvert$. | |
A regular limit cardinal other than $\aleph_0$ has a special name: it is \vocab{weakly inaccessible}. | |
Such cardinals are so large that it is impossible to prove or disprove their existence in $\ZFC$. | |
It is the first of many so-called ``large cardinals''. | |
An infinite cardinal $\kappa$ is a strong limit cardinal if | |
\[ \forall \ol\kappa < \kappa \quad 2^{\ol\kappa} < \kappa \] | |
for any cardinal $\ol\kappa$. For example, $\aleph_0$ is a strong limit cardinal. | |
\begin{ques} | |
Why must strong limit cardinals actually be limit cardinals? | |
(This is offensively easy.) | |
\end{ques} | |
A regular strong limit cardinal other than $\aleph_0$ | |
is called \vocab{strongly inaccessible}. | |
\section\problemhead | |
\begin{problem} | |
Compute $\left\lvert V_\omega \right\rvert$. | |
\begin{hint} | |
$\sup_{k \in \omega} \left\lvert V_k \right\rvert$. | |
\end{hint} | |
\end{problem} | |
\begin{problem} | |
Prove that for any limit ordinal $\alpha$, $\cof(\alpha)$ is a \emph{regular} cardinal. | |
\begin{hint} | |
Rearrange the cofinal maps to be nondecreasing. | |
\end{hint} | |
\end{problem} | |
\begin{sproblem} | |
[Strongly inaccessible cardinals] | |
\label{prob:strongly_inaccessible} | |
Show that for any strongly inaccessible $\kappa$, | |
we have $\left\lvert V_\kappa \right\rvert = \kappa$. | |
\end{sproblem} | |
\begin{problem} | |
[K\"onig's theorem] | |
Show that \[ \kappa^{\cof(\kappa)} > \kappa \] for every infinite cardinal $\kappa$. | |
\end{problem} | |