Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
\chapter{Fundamental groups} | |
Topologists can't tell the difference between a coffee cup and a doughnut. | |
So how do you tell \emph{anything} apart? | |
This is a very hard question to answer, but one way we can | |
try to answer it is to find some \emph{invariants} of the space. | |
To draw on the group analogy, two groups are clearly not isomorphic if, | |
say, they have different orders, or if one is simple and the other isn't, etc. | |
We'd like to find some similar properties for topological spaces | |
so that we can actually tell them apart. | |
Two such invariants for a space $X$ are | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\ii Defining homology groups $H_1(X)$, $H_2(X)$, \dots | |
\ii Defining homotopy groups $\pi_1(X)$, $\pi_2(X)$, \dots | |
\end{itemize} | |
Homology groups are hard to define, but in general easier to compute. | |
Homotopy groups are easier to define but harder to compute. | |
This chapter is about the fundamental group $\pi_1$. | |
\section{Fusing paths together} | |
Recall that a \emph{path} in a space $X$ is a function $[0,1] \to X$. | |
Suppose we have paths $\gamma_1$ and $\gamma_2$ | |
such that $\gamma_1(1) = \gamma_2(0)$. | |
We'd like to fuse\footnote{% | |
Almost everyone else in the world uses ``gluing'' to describe this | |
and other types of constructs. | |
But I was traumatized by Elmer's glue when I was in high school | |
because I hated the stupid ``make a poster'' projects and hated | |
having to use glue on them. | |
So I refuse to talk about ``gluing'' paths together, referring | |
instead to ``fusing'' them together, which sounds cooler anyways. | |
} them together to get a path $\gamma_1 \ast \gamma_2$. Easy, right? | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{asy} | |
size(8cm); | |
bigblob("$X$"); | |
pair A = Drawing("\gamma_1(0)", (-3,-1)); | |
pair B = Drawing("\gamma_1(1) = \gamma_2(0)", (1,1), dir(90)); | |
pair C = Drawing("\gamma_2(1)", (2,-2), dir(-90)); | |
path p = A..(-2,0)..(0,0.5)..B; | |
path q = B..(1.8,-0.5)..C; | |
draw(p, red, EndArrow); | |
draw(q, blue, EndArrow); | |
MP("\gamma_1", midpoint(p), dir(90)); | |
MP("\gamma_2", midpoint(q), dir(0)); | |
\end{asy} | |
\end{center} | |
We unfortunately do have to hack the definition a tiny bit. In an ideal world, we'd have a path $\gamma_1 : [0,1] \to X$ and $\gamma_2 : [1,2] \to X$ and we could just merge them together to get $\gamma_1 \ast \gamma_2 : [0,2] \to X$. | |
But the ``$2$'' is wrong here. | |
The solution is that we allocate $[0, \half]$ for the first path | |
and $[\half, 1]$ for the second path; we run ``twice as fast''. | |
\begin{definition} | |
Given two paths $\gamma_1, \gamma_2 : [0,1] \to X$ | |
such that $\gamma_1(1) = \gamma_2(0)$, we define | |
a path $\gamma_1 \ast \gamma_2 : [0,1] \to X$ by | |
\[ | |
(\gamma_1 \ast \gamma_2)(t) | |
= | |
\begin{cases} | |
\gamma_1(2t) & 0 \le t \le \half \\ | |
\gamma_2(2t-1) & \half \le t \le 1. | |
\end{cases} | |
\] | |
\end{definition} | |
This hack unfortunately reveals a second shortcoming: this ``product'' is not associative. | |
If we take $(\gamma_1 \ast \gamma_2) \ast \gamma_3$ for some suitable paths, | |
then $[0, \frac14]$, $[\frac14, \frac12]$ and $[\frac12, 1]$ | |
are the times allocated for $\gamma_1$, $\gamma_2$, $\gamma_3$. | |
\begin{ques} | |
What are the times allocated | |
for $\gamma_1 \ast (\gamma_2 \ast \gamma_3)$? | |
\end{ques} | |
But I hope you'll agree that even though this operation isn't associative, | |
the reason it fails to be associative is kind of stupid. | |
It's just a matter of how fast we run in certain parts. | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{asy} | |
unitsize(6cm); | |
Drawing( unitsquare); | |
MP("0", (0,0), S); | |
MP("1", (1,0), S); | |
MP("\frac{1}{4}", (1/4, 0), S); | |
MP("\frac{1}{2}", (1/2, 0), S); | |
MP("0", (0,1), N); | |
MP("1", (1,1), N); | |
MP("\frac{3}{4}", (3/4, 1), N); | |
MP("\frac{1}{2}", (1/2, 1), N); | |
MP("\gamma_1", (1/8, 0), N); | |
MP("\gamma_2", (3/8, 0), N); | |
MP("\gamma_3", (3/4, 0), N); | |
MP("\gamma_1", (1/4, 1), S); | |
MP("\gamma_2", (5/8, 1), S); | |
MP("\gamma_3", (7/8, 1), S); | |
MP("\boxed{\gamma_1 \ast \left( \gamma_2 \ast \gamma_3 \right)}", (0.5,1.2), origin); | |
MP("\boxed{\left( \gamma_1 \ast \gamma_2 \right) \ast \gamma_3}", (0.5,-0.2), origin); | |
Drawing((1/4,0)--(1/2,1), blue); | |
Drawing((1/2,0)--(3/4,1), blue); | |
Drawing( (1/2,0)--(1/2,1), dotted); | |
\end{asy} | |
\end{center} | |
So as long as we're fusing paths together, | |
we probably don't want to think of $[0,1]$ itself too seriously. | |
And so we only consider everything up to (path) homotopy equivalence. | |
(Recall that two paths $\alpha$ and $\beta$ are homotopic if | |
there's a path homotopy $F : [0,1]^2 \to X$ between them, | |
which is a continuous deformation from $\alpha$ to $\beta$.) | |
It is definitely true that | |
\[ | |
\left( \gamma_1 \ast \gamma_2 \right) \ast \gamma_3 | |
\simeq | |
\gamma_1 \ast \left( \gamma_2 \ast \gamma_3 \right) . \] | |
It is also true that if $\alpha_1 \simeq \alpha_2$ and $\beta_1 \simeq \beta_2$ | |
then $\alpha_1 \ast \beta_1 \simeq \alpha_2 \ast \beta_2$. | |
Naturally, homotopy is an equivalence relation, | |
so paths $\gamma$ lives in some ``homotopy type'', | |
the equivalence classes under $\simeq$. We'll denote this $[\gamma]$. | |
Then it makes sense to talk about $[\alpha] \ast [\beta]$. | |
Thus, \textbf{we can think of $\ast$ as an operation on homotopy classes}. | |
\section{Fundamental groups} | |
\prototype{$\pi_1(\RR^2)$ is trivial and $\pi_1(S^1) \cong \ZZ$.} | |
At this point I'm a little annoyed at keeping track of endpoints, | |
so now I'm going to specialize to a certain type of path. | |
\begin{definition} | |
A \vocab{loop} is a path with $\gamma(0) = \gamma(1)$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{asy} | |
bigblob("$X$"); | |
pair A = Drawing("x_0", (-1,0), dir(100)); | |
path p = A..(1,1)..(2,0)..(0.5,-1)..(-1.5,-0.5)..cycle; | |
draw(p, blue, EndArrow); | |
MP("\gamma", midpoint(p), dir(-20)); | |
\end{asy} | |
\end{center} | |
Hence if we restrict our attention to paths starting at a single point $x_0$, | |
then we can stop caring about endpoints and start-points, since | |
everything starts and stops at $x_0$. | |
We even have a very canonical loop: the ``do-nothing'' loop\footnote{Fatty.} given by standing at $x_0$ the whole time. | |
\begin{definition} | |
Denote the trivial ``do-nothing loop'' by $1$. | |
A loop $\gamma$ is \vocab{nulhomotopic} if it is homotopic to $1$; i.e.\ $\gamma \simeq 1$. | |
\end{definition} | |
For homotopy of loops, you might visualize ``reeling in'' the loop, contracting it to a single point. | |
\begin{example}[Loops in $S^2$ are nulhomotopic] | |
As the following picture should convince you, every loop in | |
the simply connected space $S^2$ is nulhomotopic. | |
\begin{center} | |
\includegraphics[width=6cm]{media/S2-simply.png} | |
\end{center} | |
(Starting with the purple loop, we contract to the red-brown point.) | |
\end{example} | |
Hence to show that spaces are simply connected it suffices to understand | |
the loops of that space. | |
We are now ready to provide: | |
\begin{definition} | |
The \vocab{fundamental group} of $X$ with basepoint $x_0$, | |
denoted $\pi_1(X, x_0)$, is the set of homotopy classes | |
\[ \left\{ [\gamma] \mid \gamma \text{ a loop at $x_0$} \right\} \] | |
equipped with $\ast$ as a group operation. | |
\end{definition} | |
It might come as a surprise that this has a group structure. | |
For example, what is the inverse? | |
Let's define it now. | |
\begin{definition} | |
Given a path $\alpha : [0,1] \to X$ we can define a path $\ol\alpha$ | |
\[ \ol\alpha (t) = \alpha(1-t). \] | |
In effect, this ``runs $\alpha$ backwards''. | |
Note that $\ol\alpha$ starts at the endpoint of $\alpha$ | |
and ends at the starting point of $\alpha$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Show that for any path $\alpha$, | |
$\alpha \ast \ol\alpha$ is homotopic | |
to the ``do-nothing'' loop at $\alpha(0)$. | |
(Draw a picture.) | |
\end{exercise} | |
Let's check it. | |
\begin{proof} | |
[Proof that this is a group structure] | |
Clearly $\ast$ takes two loops at $x_0$ and spits out a loop at $x_0$. | |
We also already took the time to show that $\ast$ is associative. | |
So we only have to check that (i) there's an identity, and (ii) | |
there's an inverse. | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\ii We claim that the identity is the ``do-nothing'' loop $1$ | |
we described above. The reader can check that for any $\gamma$, | |
\[ \gamma \simeq \gamma \ast 1 = 1 \ast \gamma. \] | |
\ii For a loop $\gamma$, recall again we define its ``backwards'' loop $\ol\gamma$ by | |
\[ \ol\gamma(t) = \gamma(1-t). \] | |
Then we have $\gamma \ast \ol\gamma = \ol\gamma \ast \gamma = 1$. | |
\end{itemize} | |
Hence $\pi_1(X,x_0)$ is actually a group. | |
\end{proof} | |
Before going any further I had better give some examples. | |
\begin{example} | |
[Examples of fundamental groups] | |
Note that proving the following results is not at all trivial. | |
For now, just try to see intuitively why the claimed answer ``should'' be correct. | |
\begin{enumerate}[(a)] | |
\ii The fundamental group of $\CC$ is the | |
trivial group: in the plane, every loop is nulhomotopic. | |
(Proof: imagine it's a piece of rope and reel it in.) | |
\ii On the other hand, the fundamental group of $\CC - \{0\}$ | |
(meteor example from earlier) with any base point is actually $\ZZ$! | |
We won't be able to prove this for a while, | |
but essentially a loop is determined by the number of times | |
that it winds around the origin -- these are so-called | |
\emph{winding numbers}. Think about it! | |
\ii Similarly, we will soon show that the fundamental group of $S^1$ | |
(the boundary of the unit circle) is $\ZZ$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Officially, I also have to tell you what the base point is, but | |
by symmetry in these examples, it doesn't matter. | |
\end{example} | |
Here is the picture for $\CC \setminus \{0\}$, with the hole exaggerated | |
as the meteor from \Cref{sec:meteor}. | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{asy} | |
size(6cm); | |
bigbox("$\mathbb C \setminus \{0\}$"); | |
filldraw(scale(0.5)*unitcircle, grey, black); | |
dot("$x_0$", (1.4,0), dir(0)); | |
draw( (1.4,0)..(0,1.4)..(-1.4,0)..(1.4*dir(-30))..cycle, blue, EndArrow ); | |
\end{asy} | |
\end{center} | |
\begin{ques} | |
Convince yourself that the fundamental group of $S^1$ is $\ZZ$, | |
and understand why we call these ``winding numbers''. | |
(This will be the most important example of a fundamental group | |
in later chapters, so it's crucial you figure it out now.) | |
\end{ques} | |
\begin{example} | |
[The figure eight] | |
\label{ex:figure8} | |
Consider a figure eight $S^1 \vee S^1$, and let $x_0$ | |
be the center. | |
Then \[\pi_1(S^1 \vee S^1, x_0) \cong \left<a,b\right> \] | |
is the \emph{free group} generated on two letters. | |
The idea is that one loop of the eight is $a$, | |
and the other loop is $b$, so we expect $\pi_1$ | |
to be generated by this loop $a$ and $b$ (and its inverses | |
$\ol a$ and $\ol b$). | |
These loops don't talk to each other. | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{asy} | |
draw( shift( (1,0) ) * unitcircle, grey + 5 ); | |
draw( shift( (-1,0) ) * unitcircle, grey + 5 ); | |
dot(origin); | |
path g = dir(20)..dir(100)..dir(180)..dir(260)..dir(340); | |
draw( shift( (1,0) ) * scale(0.8) * reflect(dir(90),dir(-90)) * g, blue, EndArrow ); | |
draw( shift( (-1,0) ) * scale(0.8) * g, red, EndArrow ); | |
label("$a$", (-1.6,0), dir(0)); | |
label("$b$", (1.6,0), dir(180)); | |
\end{asy} | |
\end{center} | |
\end{example} | |
Recall that in graph theory, we usually assume our graphs are connected, | |
since otherwise we can just consider every connected component separately. | |
Likewise, we generally want to restrict our attention to path-connected spaces, since if a space isn't path-connected then it can be broken into a bunch of ``path-connected components''. | |
(Can you guess how to define this?) | |
Indeed, you could imagine a space $X$ that consists of the objects on my desk (but not the desk itself): $\pi_1$ of my phone has nothing to do with $\pi_1$ of my mug. They are just totally disconnected, both figuratively and literally. | |
But on the other hand we claim that in a path-connected space, | |
the groups are very related! | |
\begin{theorem}[Fundamental groups don't depend on basepoint] | |
Let $X$ be a path-connected space. | |
Then for any $x_1 \in X$ and $x_2 \in X$, we have | |
\[ \pi_1(X, x_1) \cong \pi_1(X, x_2). \] | |
\end{theorem} | |
Before you read the proof, see if you can guess the isomorphism based just on the picture below. | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{asy} | |
size(7cm); | |
bigblob("$X$"); | |
pair A = Drawing("x_1", (-1.5,0), dir(180)); | |
pair B = Drawing("x_2", (1.5,0), dir(0)); | |
draw(A..(-2.5,-0.8)..(-2.5,0.9)..cycle, blue); | |
draw(B..(2.2,-1.1)..(2.4,0.8)..cycle, blue); | |
draw(A--B, red+dashed, Arrows); | |
label("$\alpha$/$\overline{\alpha}$", origin, dir(90)); | |
\end{asy} | |
\end{center} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Let $\alpha$ be any path from $x_1$ to $x_2$ (possible by path-connectedness), and let $\ol\alpha$ be its reverse. | |
Then we can construct a map | |
\[ | |
\pi_1(X,x_1) \to \pi_1(X,x_2) | |
\text{ by } | |
[\gamma] \mapsto [\ol\alpha \ast \gamma \ast \alpha]. \] | |
In other words, given a loop $\gamma$ at $x_1$, | |
we can start at $x_2$, follow $\ol\alpha$ to $x_1$, | |
run $\gamma$, then run along $\alpha$ home to $x_2$. | |
Hence this is a map which builds a loop of $\pi_1(X, x_2)$ | |
from every loop at $\pi_1(X, x_1)$. | |
It is a \emph{homomorphism} of the groups just because | |
\[ \left( \ol \alpha \ast \gamma_1 \ast \alpha \right) | |
\ast \left( \ol\alpha \ast \gamma_2 \ast \alpha \right) | |
= \ol\alpha \ast \gamma_1 \ast \gamma_2 \ast \alpha \] | |
as $\alpha \ast \ol\alpha$ is nulhomotopic. | |
Similarly, there is a homomorphism | |
\[ | |
\pi_1(X,x_2) \to \pi_1(X,x_1) | |
\text{ by } | |
[\gamma] \mapsto [\alpha \ast \gamma \ast \ol\alpha]. \] | |
As these maps are mutual inverses, it follows | |
they must be isomorphisms. End of story. | |
\end{proof} | |
This is a bigger reason why we usually only care about path-connected spaces. | |
\begin{abuse} | |
For a path-connected space $X$ we will often abbreviate $\pi_1(X, x_0)$ | |
to just $\pi_1(X)$, since it doesn't matter which $x_0 \in X$ | |
we pick. | |
\end{abuse} | |
Finally, recall that we originally defined ``simply connected'' as saying | |
that any two paths with matching endpoints were homotopic. | |
It's possible to weaken this condition and then rephrase it using | |
fundamental groups. | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Let $X$ be a path-connected space. | |
Prove that $X$ is \vocab{simply connected} if and only if | |
$\pi_1(X)$ is the trivial group. | |
(One direction is easy; the other is a little trickier.) | |
\end{exercise} | |
This is the ``usual'' definition of simply connected. | |
\section{Fundamental groups are functorial} | |
One quick shorthand I will introduce to clean up the discussion: | |
\begin{definition} | |
By $f : (X, x_0) \to (Y, y_0)$, we will mean that | |
$f : X \to Y$ is a continuous function of spaces | |
which also sends the point $x_0$ to $y_0$. | |
\end{definition} | |
Let $X$ and $Y$ be topological spaces and $f : (X, x_0) \to (Y, y_0)$. | |
We now want to relate the fundamental groups of $X$ and $Y$. | |
Recall that a loop $\gamma$ in $(X, x_0)$ is a map $\gamma : [0,1] \to X$ | |
with $\gamma(0) = \gamma(1) = x_0$. | |
Then if we consider the composition | |
\[ [0,1] \taking\gamma (X, x_0) \taking f (Y, y_0) \] | |
then we get straight-away a loop in $Y$ at $y_0$! | |
Let's call this loop $f_\sharp \gamma$. | |
\begin{lemma}[$f_\sharp$ is homotopy invariant] | |
\label{lem:fsharp_homotopy_invariant} | |
If $\gamma_1 \simeq \gamma_2$ are path-homotopic, | |
then in fact | |
\[ f_\sharp \gamma_1 \simeq f_\sharp \gamma_2. \] | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Just take the homotopy $h$ taking $\gamma_1$ to $\gamma_2$ | |
and consider $f \circ h$. | |
\end{proof} | |
It's worth noting at this point that if $X$ and $Y$ are homeomorphic, | |
then their fundamental groups are all isomorphic. | |
Indeed, let $f : X \to Y$ and $g : Y \to X$ be mutually inverse continuous maps. | |
Then one can check that $f_\sharp : \pi_1(X, x_0) \to \pi_1(Y, y_0)$ | |
and $g_\sharp : \pi_1(Y, y_0) \to \pi_1(X, x_0)$ are inverse maps | |
between the groups (assuming $f(x_0) = y_0$ and $g(y_0) = x_0$). | |
%Now we want to show that by taking the map $f_\sharp$, we get a \emph{functor} | |
%\begin{diagram} | |
% & (X, x_0) & & \pi_1(X, x_0) & \\ | |
% \catname{Top}_\ast \ni & \dTo^f & \rDotted & \dTo_{f_\sharp} & \in \catname{Grp} \\ | |
% & (Y, y_0) & & \pi_1(Y, y_0) & | |
%\end{diagram} | |
%\begin{ques} | |
% Check this -- we need that $(f \circ g)_\sharp = f_\sharp \circ g_\sharp$ | |
% and that $(\id_X)_\sharp = \id_{\pi_1(X)}$. | |
% Both are totally obvious once you can tell what they're asking. | |
%\end{ques} | |
%Thus in this way we've constructed a functor | |
%\[ \catname{Top}_\ast \to \catname{Grp}. \] | |
%In particular, by the fact that functors preserve isomorphism (\Cref{thm:functor_isom}), we have | |
%\begin{moral} | |
% Homeomorophic topological spaces have isomorphic fundamental groups. | |
% Category theory gives this to us for free. | |
%\end{moral} | |
% | |
%\begin{remark} | |
% Note the similarity between this and the construction | |
% of the covariant Yoneda functor (\Cref{ex:covariant_yoneda}). | |
%\end{remark} | |
\section{Higher homotopy groups} | |
Why the notation $\pi_1$ for the fundamental group? | |
And what are $\pi_2$, \dots? | |
The answer lies in the following rephrasing: | |
\begin{ques} | |
Convince yourself that a loop is the same thing | |
as a continuous function $S^1 \to X$. | |
\end{ques} | |
It turns out we can define homotopy for things other than paths. | |
Two functions $f, g : Y \to X$ are \vocab{homotopic} if there exists a continuous | |
function $Y \times [0,1] \to X$ which continuously deforms $f$ to $g$. | |
So everything we did above was just the special case $Y = S^1$. | |
For general $n$, the group $\pi_n(X)$ is defined as the homotopy classes | |
of the maps $S^n \to X$. | |
The group operation is a little harder to specify. | |
You have to show that $S^n$ is homeomorphic to $[0,1]^n$ with | |
some endpoints fused together; for example $S^1$ is $[0,1]$ with $0$ fused to $1$. | |
Once you have these cubes, you can merge them together on a face. | |
(Again, I'm being terribly imprecise, deliberately.) | |
For $n \neq 1$, $\pi_n$ behaves somewhat differently than $\pi_1$. | |
(You might not be surprised, as $S^n$ is simply connected for all $n \ge 2$ but not when $n=1$.) | |
In particular, it turns out that $\pi_n(X)$ is an abelian group for all $n \ge 2$. | |
Let's see some examples. | |
\begin{example}[$\pi_n(S^n) \cong \mathbb Z$] | |
As we saw, $\pi_1(S^1) \cong \ZZ$; given the base circle $S^1$, | |
we can wrap a second circle around it as many times as we want. | |
In general, it's true that $\pi_n(S^n) \cong \ZZ$. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{example}[$\pi_n(S^m) \cong \{1\}$ when $n < m$] | |
We saw that $\pi_1(S^2) \cong \{1\}$, because | |
a circle in $S^2$ can just be reeled in to a point. | |
It turns out that similarly, any smaller $n$-dimensional sphere | |
can be reeled in on the surface of a bigger $m$-dimensional sphere. | |
So in general, $\pi_n(S^m)$ is trivial for $n < m$. | |
\end{example} | |
However, beyond these observations, the groups behave quite weirdly. | |
Here is a table of $\pi_n(S^m)$ for $1 \le m \le 8$ and $2 \le n \le 10$, | |
so you can see what I'm talking about. | |
(Taken from Wikipedia.) | |
\bgroup | |
\footnotesize | |
\[ | |
\begin{array}{r|ccccccccc} | |
\pi_n(S^m) & 2 & 3 & 4 & 5 & 6 & 7 & 8 & 9 & 10 \\ \hline | |
m = 1 & \{1\} & \{1\} & \{1\} & \{1\} & \{1\} & \{1\} & \{1\} & \{1\} & \{1\} \\ | |
2 & \ZZ & \ZZ & \Zc2 & \Zc2 & \Zc{12} & \Zc2 & \Zc2 & \Zc3 & \Zc{15}\\ | |
3 & & \ZZ & \Zc2 & \Zc2 & \Zc{12} & \Zc2 & \Zc2 & \Zc3 & \Zc{15}\\ | |
4 & & & \ZZ & \Zc2 & \Zc2 & \ZZ \times \Zc{12} & (\Zc2)^2 & \Zc2 \times \Zc2 & \Zc{24} \times \Zc3 \\ | |
5 & & & & \ZZ & \Zc2 & \Zc2 & \Zc{24} & \Zc2 & \Zc2 \\ | |
6 & & & & & \ZZ & \Zc2 & \Zc2 & \Zc{24} & \{1\} \\ | |
7 & & & & & & \ZZ & \Zc2 & \Zc2 & \Zc{24} \\ | |
8 & & & & & & & \ZZ & \Zc2 & \Zc2 | |
\end{array} | |
\] | |
\egroup | |
Actually, it turns out that if you can compute $\pi_n(S^m)$ | |
for every $m$ and $n$, | |
then you can essentially compute \emph{any} homotopy classes. | |
Thus, computing $\pi_n(S^m)$ is sort of a lost cause in general, | |
and the mixture of chaos and pattern in the above table is a testament to this. | |
\section{Homotopy equivalent spaces} | |
\prototype{A disk is homotopy equivalent to a point, an annulus is homotopy equivalent to $S^1$.} | |
Up to now I've abused notation and referred to ``path homotopy'' as just ``homotopy'' for two paths. | |
I will unfortunately continue to do so (and so any time I say two paths are homotopic, you should assume I mean ``path-homotopic''). | |
But let me tell you what the general definition of homotopy is first. | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $f,g : X \to Y$ be continuous functions. | |
A \vocab{homotopy} is a continuous function $F : X \times [0,1] \to Y$, | |
which we'll write $F_s(x)$ for $s \in [0,1]$, $x \in X$, such that | |
\[ F_0(x) = f(x) \text{ and } F_1(x) = g(x) \text{ for all $x \in X$.} \] | |
If such a function exists, then $f$ and $g$ are \vocab{homotopic}. | |
\end{definition} | |
Intuitively this is once again ``deforming $f$ to $g$''. | |
You might notice this is almost exactly the same definition as path-homotopy, | |
except that $f$ and $g$ are any functions instead of paths, and hence | |
there's no restriction on keeping some ``endpoints'' fixed through the deformation. | |
This homotopy can be quite dramatic: | |
\begin{example} | |
The zero function $z \mapsto 0$ and the identity function $z \mapsto z$ | |
are homotopic as functions $\CC \to \CC$. | |
The necessary deformation is | |
\[ [0,1] \times \CC \to \CC \text{ by } (t,z) \mapsto tz. \] | |
\end{example} | |
I bring this up because I want to define: | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $X$ and $Y$ be continuous spaces. | |
They are \vocab{homotopy equivalent} if there exist | |
functions $f : X \to Y$ and $g : Y \to X$ such that | |
\begin{enumerate}[(i)] | |
\ii $f \circ g : X \to X$ is homotopic to the identity map on $X$, and | |
\ii $g \circ f : Y \to Y$ is homotopic to the identity map on $Y$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
If a topological space is homotopy equivalent to a point, | |
then it is said to be \vocab{contractible}. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{ques} | |
Why are two homeomorphic spaces also homotopy equivalent? | |
\end{ques} | |
Intuitively, you can think of this as a more generous form of stretching | |
and bending than homeomorphism: we are allowed to compress huge spaces into single points. | |
\begin{example}[$\CC$ is contractible] | |
Consider the topological spaces $\CC$ | |
and the space consisting of the single point $\{0\}$. | |
We claim these spaces are homotopy equivalent (can you guess what $f$ and $g$ are?) | |
Indeed, the two things to check are | |
\begin{enumerate}[(i)] | |
\ii $\CC \to \{0\} \hookrightarrow \CC$ by $z \mapsto 0 \mapsto 0$ | |
is homotopy equivalent to the identity on $\CC$, which we just saw, and | |
\ii $\{0\} \hookrightarrow \CC \to \{0\}$ by $0 \mapsto 0 \mapsto 0$, which \emph{is} the identity on $\{0\}$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Here by $\hookrightarrow$ I just mean $\to$ in the special case | |
that the function is just an ``inclusion''. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{remark} | |
$\CC$ cannot be \emph{homeomorphic} to a point | |
because there is no bijection of sets between them. | |
\end{remark} | |
\begin{example}[$\CC \setminus \{0\}$ is homotopy equivalent to $S^1$] | |
Consider the topological spaces $\CC \setminus \{0\}$, | |
the \vocab{punctured plane}, and the circle $S^1$ viewed as a subset of $S^1$. | |
We claim these spaces are actually homotopy equivalent! | |
The necessary functions are the inclusion | |
\[ S^1 \hookrightarrow \CC \setminus \{0\} \] | |
and the function | |
\[ \CC \setminus \{0\} \to S^1 | |
\quad\text{by}\quad | |
z \mapsto \frac{z}{\left\lvert z \right\rvert}. \] | |
You can check that these satisfy the required condition. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{remark} | |
On the other hand, $\CC \setminus \{0\}$ cannot be \emph{homeomorphic} to $S^1$. | |
One can make $S^1$ disconnected by deleting two points; | |
the same is not true for $\CC \setminus \{0\}$. | |
\end{remark} | |
\begin{example} | |
[$\text{Disk} = \text{Point}$, $\text{Annulus} = \text{Circle}$.] | |
By the same token, a disk is homotopic to a point; | |
an annulus is homotopic to a circle. | |
(This might be a little easier to visualize, since it's finite.) | |
\end{example} | |
I bring these up because it turns out that | |
\begin{moral} | |
Algebraic topology can't distinguish between homotopy equivalent spaces. | |
\end{moral} | |
More precisely, | |
\begin{theorem}[Homotopy equivalent spaces have isomorphic fundamental groups] | |
\label{thm:fundgrp_homotopy_invariant} | |
Let $X$ and $Y$ be path-connected, homotopy-equivalent spaces. | |
Then $\pi_n(X) \cong \pi_n(Y)$ for every positive integer $n$. | |
\end{theorem} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Let $\gamma : [0,1] \to X$ be a loop. | |
Let $f : X \to Y$ and $g : Y \to X$ be maps witnessing that $X$ and $Y$ are homotopy equivalent | |
(meaning $f \circ g$ and $g \circ f$ are each homotopic to the identity). | |
Then the composition | |
\[ [0,1] \taking\gamma X \taking f Y \] | |
is a loop in $Y$ and hence $f$ induces a natural homomorphism $\pi_1(X) \to \pi_1(Y)$. | |
Similarly $g$ induces a natural homomorphism $\pi_1(Y) \to \pi_1(X)$. | |
The conditions on $f$ and $g$ now say exactly that these two homomorphisms | |
are inverse to each other, meaning the maps are isomorphisms. | |
\end{proof} | |
In particular, | |
\begin{ques} | |
What are the fundamental groups of contractible spaces? | |
\end{ques} | |
That means, for example, that algebraic topology can't tell | |
the following homotopic subspaces of $\RR^2$ apart. | |
\begin{center} | |
{\color{red} \Huge \venus} | |
\qquad | |
{\color{blue} \Huge \mars} | |
\end{center} | |
\section{The pointed homotopy category} | |
This section is meant to be read by those who know some basic category theory. | |
Those of you that don't should come back after reading \Cref{ch:cats,ch:functors}. | |
Those of you that do will enjoy how succinctly we can summarize | |
the content of this chapter using categorical notions. | |
\begin{definition} | |
The \vocab{pointed homotopy category} $\catname{hTop}_\ast$ is defined as follows. | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\ii Objects: pairs $(X, x_0)$ of spaces with a distinguished basepoint, and | |
\ii Morphisms: \emph{homotopy classes} of continuous functions $(X, x_0) \to (Y, y_0)$. | |
\end{itemize} | |
\end{definition} | |
In particular, two path-connected spaces are isomorphic in this category exactly | |
when they are homotopy equivalent. | |
Then we can summarize many of the preceding results as follows: | |
\begin{theorem}[Functorial interpretation of fundamental groups] | |
\label{thm:fundgrp_functor} | |
There is a functor | |
\[ \pi_1 \colon \catname{hTop}_\ast \to \catname{Grp} \] | |
sending | |
\begin{center} | |
\begin{tikzcd} | |
(X,x_0) \ar[d, "f"'] \ar[r, dashed] & \pi_1(X, x_0) \ar[d, "f_\sharp"] \\ | |
(Y,y_0) \ar[r, dashed] & \pi_1(Y, y_0) | |
\end{tikzcd} | |
\end{center} | |
\end{theorem} | |
This implies several things, like | |
\begin{itemize} | |
\ii The functor bundles the information of $f_\sharp$, | |
including the fact that it respects composition. | |
In the categorical language, $f_\sharp$ is $\pi_1(f)$. | |
\ii Homotopic spaces have isomorphic fundamental group | |
(since the spaces are isomorphic in $\catname{hTop}$, | |
and functors preserve isomorphism by \Cref{thm:functor_isom}). | |
In fact, you'll notice that the proofs | |
of \Cref{thm:functor_isom} and \Cref{thm:fundgrp_homotopy_invariant} | |
are secretly identical to each other. | |
\ii If maps $f, g : (X, x_0) \to (Y, y_0)$ are homotopic, | |
then $f_\sharp = g_\sharp$. This is basically \Cref{lem:fsharp_homotopy_invariant} | |
\end{itemize} | |
\begin{remark} | |
In fact, $\pi_1(X, x_0)$ is the set of arrows $(S^1, 1) \to (X, x_0)$ in $\catname{hTop}_\ast$, | |
so this is actually a covariant Yoneda functor (\Cref{ex:covariant_yoneda}), | |
except with target $\catname{Grp}$ instead of $\catname{Set}$. | |
\end{remark} | |
\section\problemhead | |
\begin{problem}[Harmonic fan] | |
Exhibit a subspace $X$ of the metric space $\RR^2$ which is | |
path-connected but for which a point $p$ can be found such that | |
any $r$-neighborhood of $p$ with $r < 1$ is not path-connected. | |
% harmonic fan | |
\end{problem} | |
\begin{dproblem} | |
[Special case of Seifert-van Kampen] \gim | |
Let $X$ be a topological space. | |
Suppose $U$ and $V$ are connected open subsets of $X$, with $X = U \cup V$, | |
so that $U \cap V$ is nonempty and path-connected. | |
Prove that if $\pi_1(U) = \pi_1(V) = \{1\}$ then $\pi_1(X) = 1$. | |
\end{dproblem} | |
\begin{remark} | |
The \vocab{Seifert--van Kampen theorem} generalizes this | |
for $\pi_1(U)$ and $\pi_1(V)$ any groups; it gives a formula for calculating $\pi_1(X)$ | |
in terms of $\pi_1(U)$, $\pi_1(V)$, $\pi_1(U \cap V)$. | |
The proof is much the same. | |
Unfortunately, this does not give us a way to calculate $\pi_1(S^1)$, | |
because it is not possible to write $S^1 = U \cup V$ for $U \cap V$ \emph{connected}. | |
\end{remark} | |
\begin{problem} | |
[RMM 2013] \yod | |
Let $n \ge 2$ be a positive integer. | |
A stone is placed at each vertex of a regular $2n$-gon. | |
A move consists of selecting an edge of the $2n$-gon and swapping the two stones at the endpoints of the edge. | |
Prove that if a sequence of moves swaps every pair of stones exactly once, then there is some edge never used in any move. | |
\end{problem} | |
(This last problem doesn't technically have anything to do with the chapter, | |
but the ``gut feeling'' which motivates the solution is very similar.) | |