Datasets:

Modalities:
Text
Languages:
English
Libraries:
Datasets
License:
proof-pile / books /napkin /limits.tex
zhangir-azerbayev
added books
afd65d6
raw
history blame
4.05 kB
\chapter{Limits in categories (TO DO)}
We saw near the start of our category theory chapter
the nice construction of products by drawing
a bunch of arrows.
It turns out that this concept can be generalized immensely,
and I want to give a you taste of that here.
To run this chapter, we follow the approach of \cite{ref:msci}.
\todo{write introduction}
\section{Equalizers}
\prototype{The equalizer of $f,g : X \to Y$ is the set of points with $f(x) = g(x)$.}
Given two sets $X$ and $Y$, and maps $X \taking{f,g} Y$, we define their \vocab{equalizer} to be
\[ \left\{ x \in X \mid f(x) = g(x) \right\}. \]
We would like a categorical way of defining this, too.
Consider two objects $X$ and $Y$ with two maps $f$ and $g$ between them.
Stealing a page from \cite{ref:msci}, we call this a \vocab{fork}:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
X \ar[r, "f", shift left] \ar[r, "g"', shift right] & Y
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
A cone over this fork is an object $A$ and arrows over $X$ and $Y$
which make the diagram commute, like so.
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
A \ar[d, "q"'] \ar[rd, "f \circ q = g \circ q"] & \\
X \ar[r, "f", shift left, near start] \ar[r, "g"', shift right, near start] & Y
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
Effectively, the arrow over $Y$ is just forcing $f \circ q = g \circ q$.
In any case, the \vocab{equalizer} of $f$ and $g$ is a ``universal cone'' over this fork:
it is an object $E$ and a map $E \taking{e} X$ such that
for each $A \taking q X$ the diagram
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
& A \ar[dd, "\exists! h"] \ar[lddd, "q"'] \ar[rddd, dashed, bend left] \\
\\
& E \ar[ld, "e"', near start] \ar[rd, dashed] & \\
X \ar[rr, "f", shift left] \ar[rr, "g"', shift right] && Y
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
commutes for a unique $A \taking h E$.
In other words, any map $A \taking{q} X$ as above
must factor uniquely through $E$.
Again, the dotted arrows can be omitted,
and as before equalizers may not exist.
But when they do exist:
\begin{exercise}
If $E \taking{e} X$ and $E' \taking{e'} X$ are equalizers,
show that $E \cong E'$.
\end{exercise}
\begin{example}
[Examples of equalizers]
\listhack
\begin{enumerate}[(a)]
\ii In $\catname{Set}$, given $X \taking{f,g} Y$
the equalizer $E$ can be realized as $E = \{x \mid f(x) = g(x)\}$,
with the inclusion $e : E \injto X$ as the morphism.
As usual, by abuse we'll often just refer to $E$ as the equalizer.
\ii Ditto in $\catname{Top}$, $\catname{Grp}$.
One has to check that the appropriate structures are preserved
(e.g.\ one should check that $\{\phi(g) = \psi(g) \mid g \in G\}$ is a group).
\ii In particular, given a homomorphism $\phi : G \to H$, the inclusion
$ \ker\phi \injto G $
is an equalizer for the fork $G \to H$ by $\phi$ and the trivial homomorphism.
\end{enumerate}
\end{example}
According to (c) equalizers let us get at the concept of a kernel
if there is a distinguished
``trivial map'', like the trivial homomorphism in $\catname{Grp}$.
We'll flesh this idea out in the chapter on abelian categories.
\section{Pullback squares (TO DO)}
\todo{write me}
Great example: differentiable functions on $(-3,1)$ and $(-1,3)$
\begin{example}
\label{ex:diff_pullback}
\end{example}
\section{Limits}
We've defined cones over discrete sets of $X_i$ and over forks.
It turns out you can also define a cone over any general \vocab{diagram} of objects and arrows;
we specify a projection from $A$ to each object and
require that the projections from $A$ commute with the arrows in the diagram.
(For example, a cone over a fork is a diagram with two edges and two arrows.)
If you then demand the cone be universal,
you have the extremely general definition of a \vocab{limit}.
As always, these are unique up to unique isomorphism.
We can also define the dual notion of a \vocab{colimit} in the same way.
\section{\problemhead}
\begin{sproblem}[Equalizers are monic]
Show that the equalizer of any fork is monic.
\label{prob:equalizer_monic}
\end{sproblem}
pushout square gives tenor product
p-adic
relative Chinese remainder theorem!!